Discussant: Jason Mazzone (note: the approach is for
discussants to briefly present the authors’ papers, then discuss them)
Kaminski argues that European proportionality approach to
speech issues that balances them with others could be better in circumstances
where the US’s categorical approach excludes consideration of speech interests
at all.
US exceptionalism: we are trying to export our system
elsewhere.
On/off approach means that Congress can keep increasing
penalties for copyright infringement with little/no 1A constraint.
Proportionality approach would be more skeptical of criminal regime, but not
here. Would produce some judicial
oversight and would be appropriate in the US.
His comments: somewhat skeptical about differences between
proportionality and US tiered approach. You do get different-sounding opinions,
but would our Court produce different
results? Tiers are used somewhat
selectively to explain results rather than driving the outcomes. All constitutional doctrines involve
weighing; tiers of scrutiny aren’t deployed consistently across doctrines or
within them. So are differences the
product of analytical framework, or something else?
American exceptionalism: the courts do have an explanation
for why they don’t play a greater role in copyright. Specifically granted power in Constitution.
That’s the reason courts say they defer. With proportionality, there’d still be
a textual starting point.
Perhaps the 1A won’t do the work you want to do. Need to look to other constitutional
provisions—due process. 8th Amendment.
Private ordering: much happens through agreement of private
parties rather than judicial decisions.
Impact on private regimes? If
there are few litigated copyright cases, the law may not be casting much of a
shadow at all. That’s harder to correct
by altering Supreme Court’s analytical approach.
Kaminski: Motivated in part by the puzzle of Stanley v.
Georgia: court said that this speech was fully excluded from the First
Amendment, then realized that it wanted to reach back into the area. Alvarez: we’re treating 1A as an on/off
switch. So what happens when court has already kicked people out.
Q: seems like US judges are supple at getting around categories
when they want, and European lawyers seem to be able to inject absolutism. So is this path dependence, concept of
copyright as property, some other epiphenomenal factor other than the
categories themselves.
Kaminski: a lot of ink spilled about the 1A and Article I (shout-out to
me, among others, thanks!)—for the most part, the Bill of Rights restricts
Article I powers. To say that copyright isn’t subject to the Bill of Rights is
weird.
David Goldberg: ECHR has recently issued an opinion about
publication of images from the catwalk.
Nothing redeeming about the images—if they’d been involved in opening up
a general matter of public debate, like the imposition of standards on women’s
bodies. No reason not to find
infringement. What strikes him is American
exceptionalism—is that a compliment?
Pejorative? In hate speech
discussions it’s usually pejorative.
Derek Bambauer: precise copies and criminal law. Public
choice problems: individuals are never at the table; proportionality might work
there to change outcomes. Whether
infringement occurs in the first place: that’s fair use, where all the work is
being done in the US where all the weighing is being done/sensitivity to social
value of infringing use versus impact on entitlements. Is there a bifurcation
of worrying about penalties where the US is exceptional, but also fair use is more
sensitive to what you care about?
Kaminski: agrees with proportionality as check on the
legislation itself. Criminal copyright—but
there are instances of one-to-one copying that a court wouldn’t find to be fair
use but raise speech issues (see Tushnet).
Things that aren’t significantly transformative aren’t found to be fair
use, and if that moves into the criminal context, there’s disproportion.
Felix Wu: Different kinds of 1A interests. Some examples
seem different—very traditional 1A concerns if someone’s internet service is
shut down or an entire website is shut down and a bunch of noninfringing
speakers get their stuff taken down.
Article I argument doesn’t apply; we may not need the machinery of
relating copyright to the 1A. So are
these examples useful in showing a difference between the regimes? Going forward, it’s less clear that the
copyright specific concerns are central.
But what about fair use, as a different kind of 1A interest. Also distinguish interests of speaker and
listener—listeners’ interests are interests in access, and paying may be a
reasonable barrier but there’s at least an argument to be made.
Kaminski: why is the website seizure case different?
Wu: can impinge on speech of noninfringers; fair use doesn’t
even come into it—I happen to be hosted on the same server when the plug is
pulled. That is potentially an interest
of a different order.
RT: But the concerns about overdeterrence/overbreadth are the same for fair users--the risks of chill/oversuppression of noninfringers are (part of) what people fight about in the fair use context as well.
Other point: Paper makes a TM
comparison, where courts often balance the social value of the use of the mark
with the likelihood of confusion on an ad hoc basis. It's often tempting to say "the regime I study is screwed up, so maybe those guys over there have figured out a better way to deal with the problems I've identified." But I think TM scholars
generally agree that TM/free speech nexus is a mess: some courts weigh speech against confusion even
though they're incommensurable, others don’t; there are 3 different free speech
tests depending on what you’re doing. And
if anything it’s worse in the EU.
Q: balancing/proportionality just treats rights as another
interest.
Kaminski: Categories don’t dictate outcomes, yes, but they
provide a framework for judicial oversight—the thing that’s missing now is a
reason for the judiciary to even scrutinize penalties.
Q: sure, but fact and nature of oversight are two different
things.
Mazzone: Tiered approach just looks at gov’t action;
proportionality could also be a way of looking at the strength of the speech
interest. Could what you want be
achieved by changing the way we treat noncommercial copying—minimizing liability,
no criminal penalties?
Kaminski: problem is definition of noncommercial. Is it commercial when sharing substitutes for
a sale? When there’s an ad on a website?
As to affirmative weight of an interest, isn’t proposing moving all
European caselaw. Do a proportionality
approach with the stuff we now kick out of the 1A entirely.
Molly Land: critiques of proportionality come in—they can be
ad hoc. Shifting decisions to courts
raises concerns of predictability and transparency.
Goldberg: ECHR isn’t balancing 2 different rights but
implying an exception to an existing right—there’s a difference between
balancing the right to a fair trial and the press’s duty to report, or the
right to respect for privacy v. publication—going in, these things are both
important and we have scrutiny of the specific facts. But in copyright, there’s
no right to property; in principle, there’s a right to publication, and the
question is whether there is in principle a reason to limit that right.
Land: ECHR says it’s not engaging in balancing but assessing
whether what the national court did was within the margin of allowed balancing. But there is difference in considering IP a
property right and not doing so. Getting into the details might yield an
interesting agenda.
Mark Bartholomew: maybe give courts more credit—do they
really treat copyright as categorically exempt—not like fighting words or
sexual harassment; they’ve thought about fair use and idea/expression. Maybe
that’s not enough, but it’s not nothing.
Should we really be as critical about judges not recognizing civil v.
criminal? US v. Moran: intent to copy
isn’t enough; you have to intend to break the law because the dangers of
criminal penalties.
Q: we’ve moved away from prior restraints in copyright not
just as the norm but as the necessary result of every copyright violation—courts
are doing better there. Use as many
examples as possible to show which system is more protective where. Mountain
Dew ad described as the most racist ad ever; can a news organization show the
whole thing (1 minute)? Practical
answer: you may not be able to fight claim, so use a smaller chunk—but that’s
not the truth you’d give to a wealthier client.
Should the 1A be available as extra protection? Would the European system provide more
protection in the context of something like that use?
Bryan Choi: Why more or less speech protective, instead of
different? Some countries define child
pornography more broadly than we do—you might not care about that. US cares lots about Wikileaks, but not so
much about insulting the Thai king. So
there’s copyright domestic policy, and then there’s whether this is being
exported unfairly to other countries.
And finally whether proportionality should be added to the US.
Kaminski: pathology isn’t necessarily substance, it’s the
extent of punishment once it’s outside the 1A, just as penalties for child porn
possession are now out of balance with other, worse crimes.
Derek Bambauer: underdeveloped strain of cases on listeners’
rights. Usually listeners are proxies for speakers, but there are points of
interest divergence. Proportionality may
also be relevant to civil penalties—BMW v. Gore and State Farm turn out to be
just about notice, but the legislature is unconstrained about how far it can
ramp up the penalties.
Tamara Piety: if you think we’re as a practical matter more
property protective than speech protective, this trend in the US is perfectly
understandable. Compare broad powers for
forfeiture—once the gov’t takes your property, you are in deep trouble.
RT: I think I misunderstood Mazzone’s comments—I thought he
wanted to consider the copyright owner’s speech interests in the
proportionality analysis.
Wisconsin v. Mitchell as another approach to what’s excluded
but somehow still covered depending on what the government does. (Cf. the DC
Circuit case about extending the term of Mary Baker Eddy’s Science and Health.) That’s not proportionality; it reflects a
different set of concerns.
Mazzone: exceptionalism in criminal penalties: is it helpful
to think about particular expressive/deterrence costs that arise from the
nature of the federal criminal justice system—the fed gov’t’s powerful
tools. Convictions under Pro-IP act:
most of them presumably pled rather than going to trial. Lots of charges; huge risks of severe
punishments lead to smaller pleas—are these costs to expression the same in
other jurisdictions? Australia’s
criminal penalties/fines: does their system make it easier to avoid
liability/do a risk/benefit calculation and decide to fight?
Kaminski: Recent developments: Pirate Bay case in the EU
exhibited the kind of analysis she wants by asking whether the domestic
legislature had civil penalties in place that hadn’t been enough to deter
before adding criminal penalties. Also: statement from Korea about
proportionality of penalties/cutting off internet access.
No comments:
Post a Comment