Anjali S. Dalal / Administrative Constitutionalism and the
Growth of the Surveillance State
People apparently think it’s worse for the gov’t to shut
down Reddit in response to IP claims than for the government to pervasively
surveil for national security purposes.
Is this really justified, or merely something we haven’t thought
through?
Cellphone carriers received 1.3 million demands for
subscriber information for gov’t investigations. Law enforcement requests to third parties
have been growing 12-16%/year. Twitter received 849 requests globally, 679 from
the US; subpoena is sufficient, without a warrant. Third party doctrine eviscerates any privacy
interests in information you share with third parties. This may have made sense
at one time, but we now have no idea who has access to our info in any internet
interaction—so many different intermediaries touching the information. Little
understanding of who has possession and control.
CISPA: allow unprecedented sharing between private companies
and the government; creates exceptions to all privacy laws; undefined national
security purposes; no privacy minimization required; entities are granted full
immunity for any lawsuits; no FOIA available. But in addition to CISPA, there
are a slew of other laws & practices that allow gov’t surveillance.
Emerges when we elevate national security over civil
liberties; the FBI overtly acknowledges this in its priorities. Our government feels it’s doing the right
thing by engaging in pervasive surveillance. NYPD targets Muslim student
groups, framed as guarding against the threat of terrorism. Bloomberg: “this is
what you want the NYPD to do.” That’s the concern with surveillance culture: we’re
proud of it.
Is this level of gov’t surveillance new? No and yes.
Administrative constitutionalism uses agencies as frontline
of constitutional interpretation. Bill
Eskridge & John Ferejohn moves beyond descriptive account and argues that agencies
are and should be constitutional norm entrepreneurs—trial balloons. Consider the DoJ’s norm
entrepreneurship. Church Committee in
70s investigated US surveillance practices and recommended mostly speech-based
ways to reform the FBI. Other guidelines
for intelligence gathering exist—Levi Guidelines. By their nature, intelligence
investigations chill speech, so you need deliberation before such
investigations. Slowly, over 40 years,
we relaxed the restrictions, allowing more and more investigation. The
probability of stopping a crime needed to be lower. The kinds of crime covered became broader and
less associated with national security.
Freeing field agents from the bureaucracy that hindered them. By 2008,
can open investigations for “assessment” with no factual predicate.
Also, things are more secret now: citizens don’t know what’s
going on. FBI conducted 82,000
assessments on individuals, but the process of having to open a file (which had
no factual predicate) was too burdensome, so they created a pre-assessment
procedure which was even easier and less documented.
Her argument: administrative constitutionalism has slowly
shifted the balance between national security and free speech. This has allowed
the surveillance culture to become entrenched.
Q: Connect the story you told to the takeaway—this is about
norm entrepreneurs. Playing devils’
advocate: you’ve shown that a bad thing happened, but should we blame
administrative constitutionalism/norm entrepreneurship? Doesn’t it depend on
other things—there may have been popular control all along; Congress had some
ability to check in and following 9/11 Congress was supportive—not just the FBI
over/reacted. Does administrative
entrepreneurship work better with other agencies? How generalizable is this?
A: There wasn’t actually any control over the agencies;
there wasn’t anything explicit. In 2008, Mukasey finally went to Congress to
talk about the guidelines—not to get approval—and a Senator even thanked
him! This might be implicit consent, but
there was no outward check—no oversight by Congress, judiciary, public.
Q: why is agency singular? When things go off the rails is
when you only have one agency, whereas checks and balances can be created by
agencies fighting/turf battles. CALEA:
FBI wants more authority and Commerce is resisting.
A: Definitely. But civil liberties lacks a constituency.
Q: Georgetown Big Data event: General Counsel for NID argued
that it was the agencies making these decisions; when they want to share info,
they enter into complicated negotiations about who will control the info, where
it will be housed, etc. Memoranda of understanding are where privacy rules
come. But that’s a ridiculous way to replace the 4th Amendment and
public oversight. Demonstrates that agencies are convincing themselves that
they are making up the rules and taking care of us through these less observable
and more informal processes.
Q: why should the third party doctrine care about whether
the discloser knows the identity of the third parties or their number?
A: if the doctrine is based on the idea that the disclosure
is making an active, knowing, relational decision, then the predicate is gone—I
can’t hold these entities responsible for a wrongful disclosure and there’s no
way for an individual to make a rational decision about disclosing to all
these.
Felix Wu / The Ontology of Speech
Questions of the form “is X speech?” Why do we ask this question? The way in which the question is framed isn’t
a helpful starting point, if that means “is X capable of serving an expressive
purpose/conveying a message?” Anything has that capability, including a
speeding car. Teasing apart what’s
really going on: There’s a need to
balance the expressive purposes but also the non-expressive effects of this act
or activity in the world. We can’t have either inquiry alone. Resolving the conflict is hard and doesn’t
claim to have a complete answer. Because
often we ignore one of the two strands in the caselaw. Worthwhile to discuss even
if we don’t change our mind about how cases come out.
Snyder v. Phelps. Breyer: we never let people slug other
people in order to get a message out.
What’s going on in Snyder? The protestors are trying to convey a
particular political message. But the protest itself might well be understood
as directly inflicting emotional harm at a funeral. Agreement/disagreement with the political
message isn’t the source of harm—or is it?
That kind of harm results from expressive purpose rather than
nonexpressive effect. SCt makes prophylactic rule: too hard to tell difference
between emotional harm from the means of conveying the message and the
emotional harm from the message, so we give breathing room to speech. So in which situations do we need
prophylactic rules?
So, start with whether search results are speech? Search results = Google conveying a message
about what results you’d like to see? In
one sense, yes, a message is being conveyed.
It is also limiting your ability to reach other things or directing you
to reach some things over others, like a retailer deciding what to stock on
shelves—though 1A scrutiny would never apply to the latter, even though one
could claim that the retailer’s selection sends a message. By speaking in those
terms, we can start to think about what weight to grant to Google’s interest in
this case.
What about data collection?
The effects of the sense of being surveilled might itself be a kind of
independent harm that could be cognizable, but that’s also relevant with
respect to information dissemination. The harm of feeling watched also occurs
when information is used. So it’s not clear that collection and dissemination
are good lines for 1A purposes. That doesn’t mean the 1A necessarily requires
scrutiny for both of these; rather it might mean neither. Harder to draw a line between those two forms
of privacy harms.
Copyright: traditionally the view has been that copyright
has been justified because it encourages more speech. His approach: copyrighted works have
expressive potential and nonexpressive effects.
Dissemination is a way of monetizing an intangible consumptive
good. Consumption isn’t all there is,
but there are two aspects. We lose sight if we only focus on the ability to
speak through copying/creating transformative works; look at the nonexpressive
effects—the inability to monetize consumptive goods. Thinking about it in those terms might change
the 1A valence of some aspects—basic rule against copying v. idea/expression or
fair use. Might distinguish between substantially identical copies and
something else, especially w/r/t intermediary liability. Could impose obligation on ISPs to reasonably
go after substantially identical copies, but CDA immunity for everything else.
Fred von Lohmann: the first case recognizing code as speech
was Bernstein v. DoJ—a licensing requirement imposed on cryptography related
communications. What does your analysis
have to say about prior restraint?
A: Not sure—code is a clear example of this dual situation. Traditionally the bad effects are the result
of the expression; if the relevant effects are nonexpressive rather than
expressive it’s different.
Carlos Luna: is this an issue of the policies behind why we
have free speech or a disconnect between cases?
A: the sense in which I use “ontology” is questioning
whether speech exists as a thing. The thing we need to protect is not a
category of things but a purpose to which things can be put. (Paging Mike Madison.)
Luna: then shouldn’t the ultimate question be does the
construct itself meet the policy that underlies the category “free speech”?
A: yes, then you need a theory of the 1A. Wants to carve out nonexpressive effects,
things that aren’t the result of the expression in the speech act.
Blitz: would help to distinguish your proposal from a
requirement of content neutrality. Some people
might respond: what Corley does is
says that we apply O’Brien for a
content neutral regulation. You’re using expressive not just to cover
content-based but also maybe some content-neutral categories. Is it only communicative or are there other
ways to infringe on the expressive aspect of an activity?
A: Some of what I mean is content-based under current
doctrine. If we treat data/code/search
results differently—that might be understood as content-based. It’s not viewpoint discriminatory but it is
content-based. Blitz: but that might
still be nonexpressive. Wu: Google is
expressing something, but there’s also a nonexpressive aspect. That could be classed as content based but he’d
still ask about which strand is at issue. He’s trying to define a class of
things not even subject to intermediate scrutiny—that’s how content neutral it
is.
Jane Bambauer: Not a clear enough line between nonexpressive
and expressive harm. Is the only form of
expressive harm is the harm I feel from disagreement? That seems troublingly
narrow. The emotional distress of a family is not nonexpressive in her view. NYC’s decision to throw up billboards to
shame teen mothers—where would you put shame? Is that an expressive harm?
A: Disagreement is not the only form of expressive harm. It’s
expressive if it has the potential to change your mind, not your viewpoint, but
change how you think about something. Trying
to distinguish that from emotional hurt.
More along the lines of an insult—the exclusion for fighting words. It
doesn’t really change your mind about anything, just designed to convey or
induce an emotional state. The father in Snyder
wasn’t going to change his mind about anything; his emotional distress could’ve
been the result of the expression rather than the way in which the protestor
was doing it.
RT: Fred Schauer and what is thinkable—you are starting with
the edge cases; all 1A claims involve claims that nonexpressive harm is
happening, otherwise they wouldn’t be suppressing it and there’d be no rational
basis for the regulation. Why doesn’t
draft card burning have the potential to change your mind? Why don’t high drug
prices have the potential to change your mind about whether gov’t regulation of
the healthcare market is a good idea? Doesn’t bullying try to make you hate
yourself? Or perhaps try to make you
take a swing? Copyright: of course the harm comes because of the expression:
because I torrented and enjoyed The
Avengers, I don’t pay for it! [NB:
purely hypothetical. I paid for and plan to enjoy The Avengers many times!] An emotional/rational distinction also
won’t work because we only think with our emotions.
A: is the bully conveying anything? Yes. There’s no such thing as a purely
nonexpressive activity. My claim is that’s
true of anything. [And is there such a
thing as a purely expressive
activity?]
Defamation’s harm is exactly that someone else’s mind has
been changed. Economic harm of copyright infringement comes from consumption. Not claiming it’s physically possible to have
one without the other, but that they are conceptually independent.
[RT: But then they are always conceptually independent; this
is true in defamation too where we can just have the concept of economic and
emotional injury from the defamation, just as the alleged economic harm of
copyright infringement works through having consumed the infringing material. I
take it Wu’s argument is that you’re only harmed by defamation if someone’s
mind is changed, but the copyright owner is only harmed by infringement if
someone was exposed to and satisfied by—satisfaction being a result of mental
processes—the work and therefore didn’t buy it (or didn’t like the work and
would’ve bought the work before finding that out absent infringement).]
Marc Jonathan Blitz / School, Work, Speech, and CyberKant
Speech as designed to safeguard a certain sphere of autonomy
and activities related to it—Rodney Smolla: speech is connected to thought in a
manner that other forms of gratification aren’t. Steven Heyman: Boundary between the outward
realm of the state and the inward life of the individual. Social convention, historical accident, and “satisficing”
constitute First Amendment law—even if you can’t protect all activities key to autonomy, you protect enough to preserve the
citizen against the state. The
assumption is that we shouldn’t do this retail but rather wholesale: very
strong defaults even if certain things don’t fit well into abstract definitions
of expression.
Public forum doctrine began as creative move by the
courts. Kant asked how in a free society
we can be so limited in professional, military, and other ways? Can be free as
a scholar while constrained as a priest—you can step out of your role and that
defines freedom. Robert Post uses this to distinguish between democratic
legitimation and democratic competence.
The reason he focuses on speech and work is that Kant’s question remains
important. A priest can’t just step out of his role and criticize everything he
stands for and still expect to give Mass the next day. Same with schools and
workplace speech. The direction of free
speech law is shortchanging the necessary distinctions by pushing the
misleading view that speech not about political topics or topics of public
concern gets very little protection, sometimes none. This conflicts with speech
as scaffold for mental autonomy.
Internet connection: the worry is that the internet is
everywhere and can affect everything, and on that basis people will lose their
jobs and get kicked out of school.
Bambauer: Liked the idea of promoting 1A approach
satisficing in the sense that we build up categories (whether rules or
standards) to know what the safe spaces are.
A: Yes, but if we allow room for history, the problem is
that it may reduce to power politics: in 1939 the Court saw an opportunity in Hague v. CIO to make parks safe for
speech. 1A institutionalism might
provide a different way to draw boundaries, other than public forum doctrine—identifying
spaces for preserving speech (institutions) but admitting that there’s always
going to be some arbitrariness.
Anupam Chander: what do you think is your most controversial
point?
A: maybe not controversial enough. Might not have much company in liking public
forum doctrine. Kennedy has defended it v. Breyer’s balancing. Kennedy seems to like the rigor of
categories.
No comments:
Post a Comment