Contrast Effie Film, LLC v. Pomerance (S.D.N.Y. Dec. 18,
2012), which granted summary judgment to the declaratory judgment
plaintiff because any similarities
between the parties’ screenplays came from their basis in the same historical
events. Here’s what the Effie court has to say about the
creative judgments involved in doing history:
Hoehling
is not an opinion about historians’ lack of creativity.
Indeed, the critique offered by
Patry and sympathetic historians—insisting that historians put original work
into producing facts and interpretations—essentially assumes a labor-desert theory
of copyright law and argues that historians are entitled to more robust
property protection because they are performing the requisite creative
labor. See Jeanne C. Fromer, Expressive
Incentives in Intellectual Property, 98 Va. L. Rev. 1745, 1753-56 (2012);
cf. Wendy J. Gordon, A
Property Right in Self-Expression: Equality and Individualism in the Natural
Law of Intellectual Property, 102 Yale L.J. 1533 (1993). But as its opening paragraph states, Hoehling is concerned primarily with the
unique importance of maintaining a free flow of accessible historical
information: “The rationale for this doctrine is that the cause of knowledge is
best served when history is the common property of all, and each generation
remains free to draw upon the discoveries and insights of the past.” To achieve
that end, Hoehling prioritizes an
instrumental conception of copyright law and concludes that weak copyright
protections will best facilitate the creation and dissemination of new
historical knowledge.
. . . Creativity in history may
approximate the creative process of generating works of fiction, but is
arguably of a different sort by virtue of historians’ goal of accurately
representing past reality and the shared professional norms that discipline factual
and interpretive adventurousness. These
differences, coupled with the special role that historical knowledge plays in
democratic deliberation, may justify different treatment of originality
doctrine with respect to historical facts and interpretation. Further, incentive-based arguments may
ultimately support Hoehling’s approach.
For instance, given the growth of a large professoriate
motivated—professionally, personally, and financially—to generate new historical
information even in the absence of strong copyright protections, weak
protection may suffice to maximize production, or at least to push it above an
independently specified floor.
These two cases accurately reflect a division in the case
law: creative and effortful historical judgments: no protection. Creative and effortful judgments about the future,
though they are necessarily based on evidence from the past and are equally
important to democratic deliberation: fully copyrightable, no matter how small! This division strikes me as silly.
No comments:
Post a Comment