Panel 4: Intellectual Property Law II
Prof. Yaniv Heled, Georgia State University College of Law
How Abortion Politics and Technophobia Created the Distinction
Between Patentably Non-Human and Patently Human or Why Congress Desperately
Needs Scientific Advice
1987 PTO policy: claim directed to or including a human
being won’t be considered patentable subject matter. But what is a human organism or human
being? As it turns out, this is quite
difficult to figure out. Transgenic animals wouldn’t be human, nor embryonic
stem cells, according to the drafters.
Human-animal chimeras would be (human and animal cells fused). By implication, humans having one or more
genes derived from a nonhuman source.
Human clones are an unclear case.
Had trouble drafting about what they didn’t like. An animal with a few human genes = not human;
human with few animal genes = human. But
is it at the chromosomal level? How many
genes? What about animals designed to
have human characteristics—a golden retriever with a big brain, or a chimp with
a human voicebox? (Is it physically feasible
to approach this dividing line?)
What about human/machine hybrids? Implantable memory extensions—following up on
cochlear implants, which already exist.
What about brains in vats? (Does
this matter if method/machine patents for the nonhuman parts are available?)
Sentience should be the line. By definition, humans can’t have a
utility/use as per Kant; Thirteenth Amendment.
Why should we care?
Because at some point, someone is going to use this policy as a defense
when the patent is one we want to encourage.
Section 33 was passed without scientific input; sets bad precedent for
regulating science through patent law.
Prof. Kali N. Murray, Marquette University Law School
The First Amendment in Patent Law (with Prof. Erika George, University
of Utah School of Law)
Others have addressed this topic. Douglas and Breyer
construe patents as monopolies, and that has implications for how we think
about speech. Both look at using these
types of speech harms to broaden the standing of parties to challenge
patents. There’s a struggle in patent in
the 1940s that affected patent institutions and doctrine; Justice Douglas lost,
though perhaps Prometheus indicates
that his perspective has now prevailed.
When we talk about constraints on patents, constitutional
tradition is much richer than we usually recognize. The US tradition is torn
between patents as constitutional property and patents as limited
monopolies. Social obligations of the
property owner to act in responsible ways: speech claims can be premised on
access. Myriad: a set of access claims predicated on relationships
generated by patent. One claim was that
Myriad rejected a patient because it didn’t want to deal with Medicaid; a
property owner might have an obligation to grant access v. having an
unaccountable monopoly.
(I’m not sure that any of this directly matters after Golan, since the Court is obviously
uninterested in speech claims even as to copyright.)
Prof. Mark Schultz, Southern Illinois University School of
Law
Intellectual Property and Liberty
Herein of copyright and patent. Familiar arguments over property’s relationship
to/support of liberty and their relation to IP.
Though property may not always be the same as IP, the analogy is
relevant.
Common justification for property is that it promotes
liberty as well as social welfare. Three
general arguments: Property promotes autonomy; promotes the existence of a
private sector where people can arrange their own affairs/collaborate with
others; disperses power and enables people to have a political voice by giving
them a means to participate. These are consequentialist arguments and should be
understood on that basis. (Key here: Property
the institution or citizens broadly having
property?)
Property as independence.
Locke; found in development economics, e.g., Amartya Sen. Access to things people need to flourish as
human beings: security of income, ability to secure credit to cushion economic
shocks; less dependency on others/employer/government/landlord.
Creators can be disruptive, threatening: they need economic
independence to do so. Property right provides at least a place at the table to
offer some independence even if the creator sells that right. Don’t need to
worry about pleasing powerful patron.
SOPA debate was impoverished by rhetoric on both sides. Cartoonish economic argument for the law; the
argument against was largely focused on liberty v. economic interests.
Reasonable dialogue would include liberty interest at stake for creators.
Doctrinally: when we focus on the importance of independence
to individual liberty, we have to look at default doctrines of ownership in
copyright and patent. Never hastily infer work for hire arrangements. Don’t allow corporate inventorship; at least
they get the initial right that grants them some power.
Private action: property allows people to collaborate
freely, exchange/engage in private ordering.
IP works similarly. Property
rights allow inventors and creators to collaborate and to walk away. Copyright allows open source licenses and
other forms of collaboration. Every
license is its own unique form of collaboration that people have freely come
together to choose. (Really? My iTunes agreement? This seems like formalism; I have equally
agreed to the rules of the US by not emigrating, but I have a much better
chance of changing those rules by voting than of changing the iTunes rules by
negotiation or even by voting with my delete button.) This argues against compulsory collective
licensing. ASCAP etc. are private
associations, much more desirable than SoundExchange. (I wonder how many songwriters seeking to get
paid think they have a choice to enter into a relationship with a publisher and
a CRO.)
Political power: many criticisms of copyright
industries. We should remember that it
is those same economic entities that often defend the First Amendment and
freedom of inquiry in the legislature and the courts—NYT v. Sullivan; the NYT
depends on ownership of copyright to protect freedom of expression. (Except: the NYT demands WFH etc. from its
freelancers!)
Prof. Lars S. Smith, Louis D. Brandeis School of Law,
University of Louisville
Patent Liability in the Cloud
Can a defendant be liable for providing part of a system
covered by a patent? Or a method, where
different parties are responsible for different steps?
Centillion Data Sys. v. Qwest: a system for finding phone
bill on line; P has patent for system for finding information online. Can a user be liable? The patent is drafted as a system with a back
end and a front end. The back end is the tech: storage, processing,
transferring data. Front end is the user/personal computer data
processing. Court in NTP said use of a system where part of
the process happens in Canada is use in US if that’s where the system as a
whole is put into service. So the party
must put the invention into service: control it and obtain a benefit from it.
In Qwest, the question was what happened when different
people control different parts of the system. Court says that putting the
system into use and obtaining benefit was enough even if there wasn’t control.
Thus the client is an infringer. But
Qwest wasn’t liable because it didn’t put the service into use: they provided
only the back end. Are they vicariously
liable? Court says no, because they didn’t have a relationship with the
customer over the operation of the system—don’t tell the customer to do so.
What about with a method patent? Akamai v. Limelight, still pending en banc at
the Federal Circuit. Actions of multiple
parties combined: the question is whether the claim is directly infringed only
if one party exercises agency control over others. Alternatives: “directs or controls” standard;
actual or constructive knowledge that the acts are being carried out. Many method patents involve multiple parties—e.g.,
if one party tags the content and the other party uses the tags to do
something. A number of patents are
written in such a way as to involve multiple parties and are therefore not
infringeable.
McKesson v. Epic: a patent on a method of automatically and
electronically communicating between at least one health care provider and a
plurality of users serviced by the provider.
Epic is the seller of the software, but the patent deals with the
users. Epic has no direct relationship
to doctors or patients. Alleged direct
infringers are the patients. Can you be
contributorily liable for part of the process?
If the court is right that a single entity is required for
infringement, based on principal/agent law, that will exclude a number of
important cloud computing patents—valid but unenforceable. That doesn’t make any sense. He predicts that the en banc court will
incorporate common-law doctrines into law to deal with this.
Patent attorneys say that this is dumb; properly drafted
system patent gets rid of this problem.
Q for Heled: is uncertainty a feature? Maybe we like people staying far away from
what might be a human being.
Q for Murray: difficult to think of Breyer winning in patent
when he obviously lost in Golan.
Murray: Take into account the history of the First Amendment
within IP as a whole. From 1880-1952,
for patents as well as TM and copyright as well, there is a problematic
constitutional history that we’re not articulating well. Eldred
gives some space because Ginsburg distinguishes patent as a monopoly from
copyright. But Golan makes that harder.
Ginsburg is an important figure because she deferred a lot to TRIPS. If
these are international IP cases, they become more important, showing tension
between constitutional law and TRIPS.
Liam O’Melinn: Skeptical about Schultz’s transition from
property to IP. Real property is stable.
IP is unstable, and increasingly so.
Problem with legal system is protecting that instability.
Schultz: We have lots of institutions that are designed to
prevent the accumulation of hereditary power, such as real estate taxes; nuisance
doctrines; alienability rules. Thus
having an expiration date on property isn’t as surprising as you might think.
My criticism of Schultz is related to O’Melinn’s: Along with
the question of property rights v. having property, IP has only relational
value; land is more likely to be distributed/distributable in a way that allows
people to sustain themselves. I was just
reading Tasini v. AOL: he was unable to get the terms of exchange he wanted. Hard to think of property as development in
Sen’s terms unless you also think about an underlying access right so that
everyone gets an initial allocation of some value.
Schultz: debate over whether land has value until humans
impose their will; diamonds have no intrinsic value, nor does undeveloped land.
Development often requires collaboration.
(But I’m not talking about undeveloped land, nor do I think Sen
is.) He is aiming at the argument that
IP is concentrated in corporate interests. But the creator’s initial right
gives him/her some leverage in negotiations.
In land reform too, the ability to alienate/mortgage can give people
some amount of economic independence.
(Right, but in the development context this usually requires the state
to hand out chunks of land/reform ownership procedures in the first place. What I want is a better origin story: is this
really about the idea that if you are the creator you should be the owner, and
isn’t then a key question as against whom?)
Does mean liberty in the sense of positive
liberty/personhood but worried about muddying the waters.
No comments:
Post a Comment