Mark
Lemley (& Mark McKenna), Scope
Midnight
in the Garden of Good & Evil copyright infringement case. Court rejects invalidity claim: the photo has
some creative elements. So it has to go
to a jury on infringement. But we don’t tell them to filter out the elements
the photographer didn’t create—filtering is only in our instructions on actual
copying; infringement/substantial similarity is a gestalt. In TM: Reynolds
Wrap v. Handi-Foil. Court says that the trade dress is legitimate but
narrow: blue combined with light red combined with stripes. But then the court says on infringement that
juries could find infringing similarity. What’s striking about the similarities?
They say non-stick and heavy-duty, food lifts off, square footage is the same
and displayed in the same place, and Made in USA language. There is certainly similarity, but entirely
in things we’ve previously said are unprotectable under TM and shouldn’t be the
basis for an infringement finding. And then there’s the iPad design patent case
and Apple’s patent on the rectangle with slightly rounded corners. DCt denied PI based on invalidity, Fed. Cir.
says no, they’re almost certainly going to win; jury ultimately found
noninfringement (not invalidity). But one reason is that, b/c of quirk of
design patent law, they got to look at the prior art. Makes clear that they don’t
own all rectangles w/rounded corners—Apple must own something smaller than
that.
General
problem: we chop up world into infringement, validity, defenses, decided at
different times often by different decisionmakers. This creates creep in the
rights, and the only way we know to fight it is to deny all rights. What IP law
needs is an integrated scope doctrine: think about validity and infringement
and defenses this way. One IP regime has a step towards that: utility patent
has Markman hearing. What that does right: asks a single Q, what
is the scope of the patent, prior to a validity or infringement determination. Markman
focuses on words written by lawyers and not on actual invention; this is a
mistake. Patent is also not immune from the problem—it says there’s no defense
of practicing the prior art. What the
court means is probably that standards for invalidity and infringement differ
and we don’t want you to smuggle invalidity evidence that doesn’t meet the
standard into your infringement case.
But of course there should be a defense of practicing the prior art.
Integrated scope proceeding would work; could lead a case to end b/c the P is
claiming more than it has, but even if the case doesn’t end it’s an opportunity
to articulate what’s protectable about the IP right.
Greg
Vetter: Does trade secret also match as a proceeding where we do validity and
infringement and defenses all together? What about unfair
competition/misappropriation?
A: Trade
secret has been separated from misappropriation and put into IP, and that’s led
to a greater separation b/t validity and infringement; beneficial to treat it
is IP in many ways but this is not a benefit. Courts if they thought you were a
bad actor were willing to overlook the absence of a secret; we want to avoid
that sort of prejudice in an integrated proceeding.
Q: Does
estoppel help here?
A: every
once in a while, but often they don’t use it.
Reynolds Wrap is an example. Some other doctrines otherwise hard to
explain are haphazard efforts to manage this problem: “thin” copyright
requiring virtual identity—makes it harder for overclaiming to occur. Merger doctrine too.
Courts
have a natural tendency to make boxes. That’s odd way to treat a common law
doctrine. Courts are more comfortable if they feel they’re checking off what
someone else decided; less comfortable deciding breadth. But they should be.
Ramsey: is
the law ok and judges doing it wrong? Or is the law wrong?
A: we’re
not arguing the doctrines are wrong. But once we find validity—the TM was
almost functional but wasn’t fully functional so it passes—we ignore that at
the infringement stage where the elements D copied are functional. So we need
to cross the barriers.
Q: So
should judges write a claim? Should we
get rid of juries?
A: big
difference b/t ex ante claim written by lawyer and ex post determination by
judge. Much more comfortable with the latter as getting to right answer. Circumstances exist in which words will help,
especially if one has to instruct a jury.
Don’t find liability based on unprotectable similarities. Side by side
comparison could do a lot more, though Egyptian
Goddess sadly moves towards separation of validity and infringement for
design patents. It’s correct to say that
judge is more likely to get right result than juries, but one implication of
scope analysis is that some cases will fall out before reaching the jury once
you take seriously what’s actually protected.
[NB: I’m
not sure I agree w/the TM example. Arguably, if there is a secondary meaning in
a trade dress—which might not really happen in these cases—then the fact that
it’s mostly functional may put a duty on others to stay further away from the
nonfunctional aspects than they otherwise would.]
Ari
Waldman, Trust: The Distinction Between the Private and the Public in IP Law
Public/private
distinction drawing is foundational Q of privacy law, and also for IP scholars.
There are problems if either side gets too big.
In privacy/constitutional law, the public tends to crowd out the
private. But there’s also a problem in
IP when we define the public too large in the context of minimal
disclosures. Public use bar—if you
disclose/use/demonstrate invention you can’t get a patent.
Who
wins/loses public use bar cases? You can
cluster winners and losers (only about 30 so far). Lone inventor versus large
inventors have public use cases. Lone
inventors tend to lose public use bar cases; IBMs tend to win. More research has to be done, but wants to
think about possible reasons.
Rule:
inventor must maintain control over invention during the use, it’s considered
private, but if you relinquish control, it’s public. Too often, that retention of control = assumption
of risk doctrine that you run the risk someone will talk about it. Corporate
inventors have extensive legal armies/cachet that allow them to force
collaboration partners to sign confidentiality agreements.
Courts
honor norms of big inventors, not young/small ones—the latter tend to ask
friends and family. Norms of confidentiality exist but without the formality
that exists in corporate settings. Courts don’t appreciate the norms in
different social networks.
If you’re
agnostic about privileging one type over another—not saying individual is
better—it’s still not a good idea to privilege one set simply because the
doctrine ignores uniqueness/variations of social norms from network to
network. Courts privilege formally
negotiated agreements between collaborators, and arguably shouldn’t,
controlling for other factors.
McGeveran:
must first justify using inventor’s perspective. Are individual’s perceptions a meaningful
guide to what ought to be considered private? For privacy, maybe—goal is to
protect reasonable expectations. For patent, maybe not, if our goal is to get
inventions and enhance public knowledge.
A: some
evidence that purposes of patent are also met by this type of analysis. Experimentation: goal is to make the
inventions the best possible. A changed vision
of how we control public use would enhance that.
RT: how
much do these inventors know about the on sale bar? Is there any way that
tweaking the rule could incentivize them?
A: Not
sure they’re affected, but individuals generally reflect/respond to the
law.
Q: solo
inventors are often norm-jumping from informal to formal. Collaborative IBM types aren’t. One message is that we can’t switch norms
midway through the story. Can’t get a powerful exclusion right because you
started in the world of your friends.
Inventor wants patent right—powerful market-based brutal and impersonal
rights. Why not make them play the norm game from the outset in the impersonal
mode?
A: but is
that offensive to other patent law norms/frustrating other goals by making this
contextual analysis?
Q: Paper
apparently has a trade secret piece, which is stronger. Your insight from privacy is about
control. When you choose to disclose to
your inner circle, you haven’t given up on privacy—danah boyd, young people do
care about privacy but manage it differently.
Trade secrecy is a good place for that.
[Analogy to naked licensing in TM might be helpful here—the doctrine
there does recognize context.]
A: broader
conversation about relational norms of trust—read his book when it comes out!
Jessica Silbey,
IP and Constitutional Equality
Progress
Clause: one part of project comes from qualitative/empirical data, about what
people working in creative industries think progress is. Instances of market failure.
Today’s
cases: SCt. What progress do they
imagine? If SCt is thinking of deeply
rooted equality doctrines, that’s worth thinking about and responding to.
Two
dominant strains of equality doctrine in two cases—both Justice Ginsburg, but
can also be done with Aereo, Kirtsaeng, Petrella. Eldred:
Aristotelian equality promise of likes being treated alike. Classic neutrality—similarly
situated classes treated the same; difference needs justification; deference
goes up as the class gets less suspect. 7 members of Court said that Congress
could extend 20 years to existing, not just future, copyrights. What incentive rationale is there? What limit
is there on that? The Court didn’t have factual explanations for this—a lot of
hypothesizing, which is fine under rational basis, but what really might have
been going on is an understanding of the value of formal neutrality in
application—treating all copyright owners the same. Language: parity,
alignment, even-handedness, existing and future copyrights “alike.” Harmony,
sameness—these words show up again and again.
Personalization of the benefit for copyright owners is not about
incentives but about the dignity of equal treatment.
Rudimentary,
and there are problems with the theory. Ignores the democratic flaws in
copyright legislation; assumes all authors are similarly situated when they’re
not. Failed to consider those left out,
while enacting a story about inclusiveness. A classic problem of formal
neutrality. We talk about this a lot in equal protection law. Justice Ginsburg knows that all too
well. Just application of neutrality
depends on starting line being relatively equal for all those being compared.
Golan is actually about
antisubordination. © restoration for foreign works in public domain because of
failure to comply with formalities. Court saw 104A as reparations for unfair
losses in previous years. Reciprocation—foreign
works put on equal footing w/US counterparts. Not about treating likes alike;
it’s the other side of the coin: justifying antihierarchy approach where
constitutional equality dehierarchizes unjust status differences. Targeted special benefits are ok—affirmative action
reverses unfair deprivation. Language: foreign
authors “subordinated” to domestic; 104A is a “remedy,” restoring authors to
the position they would have had—that is language from discrimination
cases. Critiques Breyer as American exceptionalist,
which also resonates.
Problem
with that too. Ginsburg says: Q is
whether users must pay or limit their exploitation to fair use. Rights must be obtained from marketplace, as
they must be from US authors. This sounds like equal pay for equal work. Contrary to equal pay laws, where there are
no losers but discriminators and about whom we don’t care, 104A causes real
harm to people who didn’t do anything wrong—now forced to pay. Leveling up
ignores harm to stakeholders who don’t have political power—misses bigger
picture about benefits for public domain, thinking © benefits only authors and
not the public.
Petrella: also a direct response to the
Lily Ledbetter case in which Ginsburg dissented. Is this fundamental to the argument?
Fortuitous? Is it a complement to or
displacement of a traditional property framework? What does it have to do with
Progress at all? Blank check to Congress?
Vetter:
would this mean that in AIA the fact that we left patents through March 2013 as
first to invent and not first to file would be potentially unconstitutional?
A: not
trying to determine constitutionality, but explaining cases through other
frameworks, not necessarily as predictive or normative. From perspective of IP
on the ground: SCt cases read strangely, at level of generality that feels
unrooted.
RT: Golan argument,
you say that this ignores harm to the public.
But they were wrongdoers in this account, right? Compare Mark Twain/piracy discourses—wrong
even if legal.
Jonathan
Mazur: Ginsburg seems to be imputing normative judgment to Congress—meant to
treat likes alike. Does that make a difference v. constitution?
A: It’s
not that someone made an equal protection argument. Golan
is right w/r/t deference. But then why
is the language there? Equal protection
jurisprudence is a leaky doctrine. It
changed constitutional law generally, became a fundamental value. Q is whether it
does here.
Q: Why use
a construct that is a red flag to colleagues?
A: That is
exactly what happens in Aereo—Scalia calls
the majority out. Kirtsaeng is a
split, and looks more like a substantive equality case. Might see more splits/disputes over proper
framework.
Q: Lexmark: treat them all the same? [That’s super interesting, especially since
you’re seeing resistance in the lower courts to applying Lexmark to §43(a)(1)(A) even though the opinion clearly instructs
that should happen.]
Gerhardt:
is equality the new “traditional contour”?
A: if so,
we need to put pressure on how the lines are drawn, how the class is defined.
Constitutional lawyers think a lot about that.
We need to do the same.
Gregory
Mandel, The Plagiarism Fallacy in Intellectual Property Law
Public
perception: IP law designed to prevent plagiarism. Experiment—trying to figure out what American
adults using Mechanical Turk thought about copying. Copying someone’s creative product: 20%
conditionally acceptable; 78% not acceptable.
Why/why not: 78%: ethical/moral. 6% mention any legal basis. Response examples: “copying someone else’s
work and taking credit for it is theft.”
“People should get credit where credit is due.” Credit/misplaced attribution was the greatest
concern.
Popular
understandings of purpose of IP law.
Developed brief explanations of incentives, natural rights, expressive
rights, and plagiarism; participants asked to rank by agreement w/them as
justifications for IP protection. Plagiarism: 37% incentives and natural
rights, 26% each, expressive rights 11%.
In-depth
look towards IP in specific contexts: creative subject matter: book, music,
painting, medicine, electronics, software. Type of copying: idea/expression
(not full product)/copying creative product.
Perspective: what law is and what law should be.
Results:
plagiarism fallacy appears to be rooted in and partly a cause of widespread
perception that IP rights are too strong and too broad. In identical scenarios, participants believed
copying should be permitted to a greater extent than law allows.
In each
subject area, the copying in the idea condition would be permissible, complete
copying not; expression (e.g., copying some qualities and chorus of song but
not entire song; reverse engineering and duplicating patented chip). Higher numbers = more in favor of copying—largely
in favor of copying ideas. But in 4/6 partial copying scenarios, public
believes copying should be allowed, and for music, complete copying is ok, and
books and medical devices above 40%. So
preferences are highly contextual.
Tested
mitigating factors: copying for educational purposes; noncommercial;
permission; attribution. Results: baseline: permission made it nearly ok to
copy. Attribution, educational use, and
noncommerciality all should reduce infringement liability. All differences statistically
significant. Educational use generally
does better than attribution. The
majority of people think that simply providing attribution should enable the
free copying of intellectual works/inventions—not just downloading a song on
the internet but other creative works too.
Exposing
the plagiarism fallacy explains some puzzling behavior: YouTube videos that say
“no copyright infringement intended” (or even “no copyright intended”). Nonresponse to “infringement is theft”
campaigns. Many people may agree with “theft,”
but have a different understanding of the meaning of “theft” than IP owners.
People hear: don’t claim credit for someone else’s creative endeavors, and they
think, “I can do that.” People aren’t
dismissive towards IP rights, but they understand them differently.
Further
findings: public is ignorant of IP law.
Multiple choice quiz—average of 4/10 right, 1.5 above chance. Knowledge of IP law doesn’t affect opinions
about what the law should be: if they did really well on the quiz, they still
don’t change opinions about what IP should protect, suggesting that info
campaigns are unlikely to change views.
The public views patents and © relatively similarly. Answers across subject matters vary widely,
but that variation seems subject matter dependent, not about artistic domain v
inventive domain. Variation isn’t across
copyright/patent divide.
Demographic
variation in preferences. Older people,
women, conservatives, and wealthier people tend to believe in stronger IP
rights, and tend to report greater self-compliance w/IP rights than alternate
groups.
Silbey:
Findings on software: where we think rights should be weakest, public thinks
rights should be strongest. Does that
have to do with industry status, distance from industry (people paint).
A: medical
scenario involved vaccine, not familiar.
(Silbey says: that saves people, is understandable.) Scenario was someone who writes a computer
program copying functionality—reverse engineering.
RT: so the
people who say they believe in strong IP rights, do they believe in the
plagiarism norm very very strongly, or do they believe something else? How do
they respond to things like educational/attributed use?
A: Only
difference we really saw: People who believe in expressive basis favor weaker
rights. We are going to study
differences in response to changed scenarios.
Sheff:
most people on MTurk are consumers and not producers. If you think IP is
distributive, it might not be persuasive to have respondents only from one side
of the distributive problem. Could you manipulate respondents to be creators, like
Sprigman, Fromer, and Buccafusco?
A: our
hope is to run the same survey with creators.
Heymann:
not surprising that people think IP is plagiarism because their first
encounters in research papers involve attribution norms.
Q:
relevance of TM examples?
A: we were
surprised by plagiarism results, but TM is about attribution.
Lemley: if
we think this is troubling, is it the law that should conform to people’s views
or should people be educated about the law?
A: doesn’t
take the position that belief should = law. We can have other objectives.
Strong point: represents dominant view among users and some creators. Can’t
expect IP system to function the way we want for incentives if there’s this
widespread disconnect about the law.
Think about how we are going to get greater penetration among the
public. Look at creators. [We could create an absolute educational exemption. That might not have a huge effect on
incentives but could really help.]
No comments:
Post a Comment