DePaul University College of Law
Graeme Dinwoodie and Mark Janis: Welcome and Introduction
Dinwoodie: boundaries are not a new issue, though more
salient of late. Why more acute of
late? Causes are problems connected to
subject matter and problems connected to scope of rights. One response is to try to roll back some
subject matter/scope. There may be
justifications for those extensions, though, so keep that in mind.
Teller’s lawsuit
for copyright/TM infringement over copying his rose trick. Most people had a gut feeling that the TM
claim was wrong, but different intuitions about how to get there or whether the
doctrine could bear that. Does the
doctrinal rule we articulate need to match up transparently with the “why” or
normative justification for the limit—functionality, for example?
In Europe, for example, they’re considering revising their
version of functionality, and it’s bubbling in the US too. French bill on right to use TM in certain
ways in connection with generic versions of drugs.
Janis: Turns out to be surprisingly complicated to teach
students to distinguish copyright from TM.
Sign of fundamental conceptual difficulties. In-house counsel’s reaction: isn’t it
wonderful how we can create these cumulative webs of protection—where design
fails, claim copyright, where that fails, claim TM, and so on.
Session 1: Boundary Policing: Rationales and Sources of Law.
Introduction: Bob Bone
Boundary problems exist in any multiple legal regime. We think of copyright and TM, TM and patent.
But there are other IP regimes—false advertising, right of publicity, even
contract when licensing is at issue.
Functionality is a prominent aspect; genericity; contributory
infringement in some contexts where one concern is restricting generics with an
expired patent—Inwood Labs wanted to
avoid a broad remedy there.
Boundary problems/doctrines are flexible. Cumulation of rights—costs include
transaction costs of evaluating all potential legal regimes, and uncertainty
about what liability might be which produces chilling effects. Conflict of rights: TM conflict with patent/copyright. One way to think about conflict is as of a
right to copy. Finds that rhetorically
useful but analytically unhelpful. Doesn’t
think there’s a natural right to copy; after Golan hard to say there’s a constitutional right to copy, though perhaps regulatory schemes under cl.8 have
some preference to those under the commerce clause when there’s a conflict. Are there policy conflicts between the two
legal regimes? A kind of Kewanee preemption analysis, even in
non-preemption contexts. (Isn’t this
conflict preemption?)
First, you want to make sure there’s a serious TM case—serious
consumer harm of the kind TM law is meant to stop. If there’s still a conflict with freedom to
copy, such as with an expired patent, ask why Congress wanted freedom to copy
there. Maybe to incentivize downstream
innovation, or to facilitate competition and get rid of deadweight loss. Maybe a direct competitor is copying, in
which case downstream innovation is less of a problem, so competitive necessity
should be the test; maybe it is follow-on innovation as with the Jay Franco
circular towel. (Hunh?) Then you have to choose which body of law you
should prefer, and that takes him back to the Constitution, which may help
break ties in favor of patent/copyright over TM/commerce.
Barton Beebe
One reason we care about boundaries is that we care about
the boundary between unfair competition and IP.
TM might be better thought of as unfair competition. Thus our discussion is different from a
patent/copyright boundary discussion. A European approach wouldn’t link
attribution right with expiration of the copyright.
What is the just-so story we tell ourselves about the rise
of these fields? These laws began long
ago, independently of one another. Unfair competition was separate from
patent/copyright, but then started butting up against each other. What are the
cases where the judges first had to deal with this and set the terms of the
conversation? Was it the rise of “goodwill”? Comparatively, is it different in other
countries?
Why are we asking these questions now? Dastar
is his impetus (right of publicity in the background). What do we do as claims start being made over
public domain works? He’s sympathetic to
authors’ rights, and listing names as a matter of tradition. Finally, level of abstraction. If we talk
about dividing patent law into rules/tech sectors, we could also talk about
boundaries w/in copyright law or w/in trade dress (packaging/design)—who benefits
from moving up and down that scale in making divisions—which industries?
Capital v. labor? Americans v. Europeans?
Primary Discussant: Robert Burrell
Why are IP lawyers obsessed with boundaries? Other parts of the legal academy attempt to
break down boundaries, e.g. imposing liability in new tort situations. Is it just the expectation that works will
fall into the public domain at a particular time and we don’t want that
expectation thwarted, most obviously by TM? Is it changes in the way
goods/services are being marketed—growth in character branding/merchandising? Popeye is licensed since 1915; can you put
his image on your own brand of spinach just because the image is in the public
domain?
Boundary concerns have always been with us in IP. But scope expansion and subject matter are
important—if we didn’t have post-sale confusion, would the Louboutin case be as disturbing?
If plaintiff really had to show confusion among consumers at the point
of sale, the dangers associated with a passing off action would look different
(he suggests this might be true in UK).
New forms of TM don’t fit very comfortably with the aim of TMs. Take graphic representations in registrations.
If you look at defendants’ arguments in Louboutin,
there’s real doubt about what it is that the plaintiff is seeking to claim.
Likewise with the European registration, they seem to be trying to claim the
idea of a red soled shoe in any particular shape, which shouldn’t be allowed. If you wanted to solve the problems of
graphic representations of 3-D marks, you’d want to move more towards a
patent/design system, with a detailed textual representation whose scope would
be interpreted rather than a sort of bizarre drawing.
Boundary between TM and consumer protection. In Australia:
logics from registered TM system have been taken to consumer protection without
further analysis. Junior user can never
sue senior user even with lots of confusion—adopted in consumer protection
field. Should think harder before we do
that.
Mark Lemley: Why now?
Dastar is symptom and not
cause. Should treat right to copy as a
co-equal participant in the system; otherwise competition simply retreats as
rights expands. You need some theory of, if not a constitutional right, a
social value of competition worth achieving.
Historically, we should think more about why we threw out
the doctrine of election of rights. The
other thing to put on the table is the state/federal axis. State TM law has
largely receded, but there are still circumstances, especially around dilution,
where state laws are significantly less restrictive than the federal system. State
TM rights that do go further, he thinks, ought to be preempted; there are cases
from the 1940s saying this but they then disappear.
Annette Kur: Cumulation—what do we call that? May be 2 different IP rights pertaining to a
physical object: a patented machine with a TM applied. That’s probably not
anything we care about. As long as we can distinguish the machine and the mark,
we don’t worry much. The closer the two get, though, the more we worry: if the
rights pertain to the same aspect of the physical object—design patent,
copyright, TM all covering the same feature.
Even there, we wouldn’t have so much reason to worry if the difference
persisted in the immaterial idea (TM only covers conveying distinct commercial
origin; design/copyright only covers aesthetics). But if these two also merge,
so you can’t find a clear distinction, then you have the real disturbing
cumulation.
Conflict of rights: what might seem to be a conflict might
not be such a problem if the aspects that justify the protection granted under
one regime are actually sufficiently weighty to justify the result that we
get. If the patent in the machine
lapses, there’s no reason for TM right to lapse as long as it’s fulfilling its
function. Even after the lapse of design protection, if use of the shape in
commerce would confuse customers as to source, that might still justify
protection.
Mark McKenna: All
IP is really about unfair competition. The boundaries of all the IP regimes
individually are deeply informed by competition norms. One concern about the
overlap is that we think about things in silos. We think very carefully about
the boundaries of patent in the AIA, with no consideration about how those
boundaries would be undermined by TM law etc.
Thrown out of whack if you can circumvent by swiveling to the next IP
regime.
Right to copy: Doesn’t want to get bogged down in right v.
norm, but we generally discuss the background rule of free copying in the
economy and IP rights are exceptions, which is why we need to give reasons for
them. Dogan has said: we’ve flipped the
presumption in many cases, requiring defendants to give reasons why it’s ok to
copy in this particular case. That’s the
risk of not using the language of rights and freedom.
Lionel Bently: History—modern conception of IP is completely
inextricable from boundary problems. Emergence of different categories arose
from trying to figure out what the essences of the categories were—what was the
difference between design and patent, and design and copyright? Led to an
articulation of the essences: design (form), patent (innovation), copyright
(creativity). Period leading to 1875 TM
registration act—you see people registering labels under copyright law, and
registering them as designs. People use
what they think is available. Highlights
that the categories are themselves born out of boundary problems, attempts to
purify design and patent that help spur emergence of TM. Then the registration system/bureaucracy
leads people to think of TM as part of a collective body of rights. Only in last 20/30 years there’s actually
been an IP category in the law rather
than a category of laws. Copyright is used to supplement/reinforce TM
as well—for example in the Arsenal
case or in its use to prevent importation/reimportation of grey-market goods.
Janis: similar attempt to use design patent in the US before
there was federal TM protection.
My comments: History: people weren’t very sure—design ends
up in the US patent regime instead of copyright basically by accident; there
may be something more to the constant media confusion about which is which than
we want to admit. Bently’s point about
categories born out of boundary problems reminds me of Adrian Johns’ argument
that the concept of copyright is born out of the concept of piracy rather than
the reverse.
Question for Bone: follow-on innovation as with the Jay
Franco circular towel. He explains: He
meant that the case stands for the proposition that basic design elements
should be unprotected—an idea/expression thing in the context of TM.
My reaction to Kur’s point about how some conflicts aren’t
that troubling if the second, unlapsed right is still serving its own purpose: Two
possibilities it seems to me: maybe we don’t trust confusion determinations in
exotic mark situations (Wal-Mart—courts
are likely to get this wrong so often that the game isn’t worth the candle--how
does this work in a European/registration system with a double identity rule in
place, where it might not be functioning as a mark in reality but it’s
registered?) and maybe we want to incentivize adoption of marks that don’t
create that risk in the first place.
Graeme Austin: TM serves a communicative function, which is
why we might be nervous about nontraditional marks. If we take TM seriously, the only message is “I
stand behind these goods,” and so idea/expression means something different
when we talk about a right to copy. The
idea when there is a need/right to copy is that the thing constituting the TM
actually also says something
else. A tacit assertion by TM
proprietors: I have the right to communicate source in any way I choose. Austin would interrogate that structurally:
why make it easy to claim the right to communicate in a particular way if there
are good alternatives?
Bill McGeveran: We accept overlapping claims a lot in
law. The cumulation problem reduces to a
conflict with freedom of action.
Dinwoodie: Can look at purpose—are the regimes doing
different things? He finds that largely unpersuasive
because you can usually make out a case that the design is still indicating
source. Or you can look at what aspects
are protected. Or you can look at
outcome, which he thinks is the real issue.
Is the use enjoined in a way that looks like enjoining reproduction in
copyright?
In conflict of laws, you’re talking about boundaries of a
different source. “False conflicts” are
deemed so by weighing interests. Some of
that methodology might be useful—comparative impairment. Which interest will be more adversely
affected by not having its rule applied?
Some of this in Vornado or Duraco—trade dress isn’t all that
significant a part of TM while patent is very important. He thought that approach was too categorical, but should ask questions about
whether, for example, a TM claimant could avoid the problem by picking a
non-design mark, which would be evidence that the TM interests were less
weighty than the copyright/patent/right to copy interests.
Laura Heymann: Striking that we don’t see more copyright claims
in merchandising in the US. Not aware of a lot of cases along those lines, but
you’d think TM owners would turn to them readily as copyright claims.
Jeremy Sheff: note that LV has been doing that a lot.
Heymann: but not Boston
Hockey.
Jessica Litman: in the earlier cases, there were notice
problems. (Which suggests a path
dependency: lawyers were trained to do TM proceedings/seizures, and as McKenna
points out TM gave them everything they wanted, so why bother?)
Heymann: changing view of disclaimers and their
effectiveness; might be a preferable remedy to an outright ban. Scholarly work saying disclaimers don’t work
comes from the TM bar; there’s more work to do.
Also interested in the “right to copy.” Different traditions have different baselines
about what competition means. US-focused
view; and a view that thinks of IP largely as a commodity to be traded, rather
than as involving personality interests. Also tied to rhetoric of copyright “bargain.” Are all bets really off after the term ends?
Michael Grynberg: Louboutin
in a world without post-sale confusion.
Underscores that when we think about boundaries they’re not just a way
of mitigating IP problems, but they have a salutory effect of their own. There’s
a benefit to the quality of the regime. Smith v. Chanel: assuming the court was
right that the defendant’s wrong could be addressed through false advertising
claims, we had some clean understanding of nominative uses. Now we see problems with the more recent
cases, but the sense of a boundary made TM law better, independent of its
relationship to other doctrines/spillovers.
Bone: thinks right to copy obscures the analysis. What are the underlying policies?
Robert Burrell: agrees that we should consider incentives
for potential TM claimants to choose marks that don’t interfere with
competition. In a registration based system, though, registries have abandoned
any role in protecting the public interest.
How the registry should deal with the title of a work, for example: the
registry doesn’t want to deal with the idea that it might have to reject marks
where there might be interference with public interests. Now they’ve said that they’ll police for
titles of public domain works, but not works still in copyright.
Sheff: Is competition a positive or a residuum? Opposed to IP or inherent in it? Also, what’s being communicated by something
in which IP rights are claimed?
Competition means something different in TM than in other
forms of IP. Subject matter as form of
info: in TM, the info is about something
else—the subject matter of the exchange over which we want to have
competition. That’s not true in
copyright, patent, or design, where the subject matter of the exchange is the
info itself. Implications for how you look at the competition values you’re
trying to protect. Maybe you can have competition over the subject matter of
exchange without strong IP protection for the marks that indicate source or
other features of the goods, in ways you couldn’t necessarily promote competition
where the subject matter is the goods themselves.
Kur: Finds it useful to ID the types of cumulation, which may
differ. The closer the points to which the rights are attached come, the more
problems we’re likely to find. That’s
just a starting point—can still have problems if the purposes are different. With double identity rule, no possibility of
balancing other interests like competition. Asymmetric convergence: the
requirements for protection tend to converge—rights are granted simply because
what has been created is different from what has come before, regardless of degree
of creativity or degree of distinctiveness—but the limitations remain the same,
tailor-made to each distinctive right.
Then it’s likely that things can go wrong.
McKenna: Dinwoodie’s conflicts analysis: in most
functionality cases, and many cases we’re talking about, TM values would almost
never be seriously harmed by giving way. We’re not talking about TM v. nothing,
we’re talking about TM in design v. TM only in labeling. Remedies could be directed to packaging,
labels, etc.
Dogan: gravitating towards a TM defenses approach, as a
pragmatist. We’ve been waving our hands for so long, saying courts are getting
wrong in defining the affirmative rights.
TM isn’t about free riding, but about preventing injury! There’s a deeply held value among
courts/legislatures against free riding.
(I have lots of thoughts about the relationship of this trend to the 1%
v. the 99% and whose contributions to collective value get noticed and whose
are invisible/background/fair game for appopriation, but set that aside.) Whether normatively justified or not, when
courts don’t see a compelling value on the other side, it seems unfair. There are lots of successes on the defense
side in the last decade, but we’re still waving our hands because (1) courts
can erect theoretically protective doctrine, but if it’s fact intensive enough
the risk of strike suits & C&Ds chills anyway, and (2) we have a
different shared idea about the role of free riding. Courts think free riding is bad except when they see the competition
reasons—descriptive mark that people need access to. We need to shift our focus to be more
effective: interests of particular classes of defendants in access.
Rebecca Tushnet: A bit of feminist/Foucauldian theory: Boundaries
exist to be penetrated. This isn’t
just done by rights claimants making TM claims that we think should be
copyright claims (Dastar). For Graeme: raises issues of territoriality
and the questions I had last week about Grupo
Gigante’s nonstatutory implication of a special “well-known marks” test for
confusion—the penetration of
extraterritorial meaning in order to address what the court feels is unfair
copying (note that copyright territoriality is very different). As
Burrell said with the logics of the
regimes in Australia, so here. Materiality
crept out of TM to false advertising and should return back to TM; creativity;
fair use and the parody/satire distinction.
The paired copyright/TM claims like Teller’s, the lawsuit against John Carter of Mars comics—we tend to think
that if the copyright claim fails the TM claim must necessarily fail, so we’re
borrowing the same logic of penetration (if it’s copyright fair use, it’s
necessarily nominative fair use) if only by default.
I’m also interested in non-IP regimes (surprised to hear
Bone refer to false advertising as an IP regime) such as false advertising, antitrust
(which used to be thought of a significant limit on the scope of TM rights;
something happened internal to antitrust that removed it as a boundary
constraint, but there are still issues of market definition capable of crossing
boundaries, as Lemley & McKenna argue), defamation, and commercial speech
doctrine. Why didn’t courts initially
notice that dilution was defamation-lite?
The Supreme Court has been active in preventing evasion of defamation
restrictions in other areas, e.g., intentional infliction of emotional
distress. The First Amendment can useful
in establishing lexical priority of defamation-type rules, with liability only
allowed when strict defamation-type constraints are satisfied (Mattel v. MCA),
though that is not applied rigorously as yet (V’s Secret). Why not ask similar questions about the right
of publicity?
Jeremy Sheff: Competition, framed positively or negatively;
problem of drawing boundaries is determining whether and on what terms
competitive copying will be permitted. Who
benefits? Maybe we think competition
increases welfare; maybe we think restrictions on competition should be
defended against rent-seeking, which is often/inevitably attendant on creation
of rights. Moral/personality interests
may also need to be taken into account.
So we ought to ask: who has an interest in a given set of facts?
Relationship between rhetoric/parables of competition and
the application of those to particular cases.
Dogan’s right that moral intuitions loom large.
McKenna: Sheff notes that the moral intuition of courts,
when they have to apply things in a case by case way, leads to results with
troubling structural outcomes; instinct that the benefits and burdens are
different in different cases leads courts to want doctrinal structures that
offer them freedom of movement in individual cases. But that doesn’t work. The best structures prevent courts, at least
presumptively, from having to engage in balancing in any particular case. The strong form of Traffix: doesn’t engage in balancing of competitive need for this
particular competitor, but asks more generally if this is useful for the
product. The alternative tends to get
bogged down in “is this def’t a bad guy?”
Eric Goldman: TM is fundamentally an equitable
doctrine. Funky linedrawing based on
intuition is inevitable. If we don’t want that, we need to build in bright line
boundaries.
TM is designed to fix only one problem: certain defects in a
competitive marketplace. There are
limiting doctrines: defamation can sit side by side with TM, but only if we
think of it as solving a different problem.
Why are we so casual about pleading in the alternative? Why do we allow four different doctrines
aimed at the same problem? He hates a
dozen causes of action based on the same facts.
So wasteful. If any one gets past
a motion to dismiss/for SJ, the costs go up for not much extra benefit.
Lemley: He’s a standards guy more than a rules guy, so he
disagrees with McKenna somewhat. (He
liked TM use, McKenna points out.) The
more formal the structure, the more brittle it is for changes in the facts or
the law. Abstraction is necessary for
when things like keyword ads show up.
Also true of defenses. We did a creditable
job of writing defenses in the TDRA, but some things just won’t fit within
those categories but defenses are still appropriate, and the more we write
specific lists the more judges are likely to abdicate their role of figuring
out what actually makes sense of the law (*cough*Silstar*cough*). At the end
of the day, juries are still making substantial numbers of TM decisions (though
there are some bench trials) if they go to trial—it makes a difference. If we’re asking juries factual questions, the
jury is unlikely to pay a great deal of attention to boundary questions; not
likely to be asking whether this fits into a TM box or a copyright box.
Dogan: spirit of her project is really not just about
defenses but limiting doctrines in TM more generally. We need to be more
articulate about the social value promoted by certain uses. In many cases, it’s better to think about
encouraging courts into thinking about internally limiting doctrines, not just defenses.
Aesthetic functionality has an internal boundary-drawing
inquiry that’s trying to draw lines between source-identifying functions and
intrinsic values of the products. The indeterminacy of this inquiry is
incredibly frustrating. Courts are asking themselves to disentangle these
roles, and it’s really an impossible task.
As we think about boundaries, ask whether there is any satisfying
alternative that we could offer. The
basic inquiry is just unmanageable.
Jessica Litman: For Goldman: what does it mean to say TM is
designed to fix only one problem? Not historically descriptive of the design.
Goldman: Fixing a problem of competition in the market where
info presented to consumers causes them to make wrong choices. This is a normative proposition about what TM
should be trying to do.
McGeveran: Pleading in the alternative is an aggressive
response to an ossified system that had a writ for everything and you used the
wrong one at your peril—inflexible, encouraged gamesmanship. Thought: same behaviors could implicate
multiple legitimate concerns of the law; why force someone to pick one legal
theory. Not problematic/wasteful/inefficient
if attacking different troubling aspects of the same behavior. Doctrinal tidiness as itself a goal seems
unnecessary. Might help keep the home
doctrines tied to their animating principles, but that seems a long way away
from one doctrine per customer. Also
runs into problems of design—how do you figure out what the plaintiff’s claim
is at an early stage? Looking for
essence is appealing but he’s not sure it delivers.
Grynberg: in favor of rigidity: we talk about the value of
adaptation, but it’s adaptation that allows expansion in the first place. Thus
we want some baseline to keep courts from going wild. What’s left if there’s no right to copy? The intuition that free riding is wrong! Never understands what restrictionists think
we get from embracing standards.
Dinwoodie: judicial method.
In the past 20 years, behavior is different than the past 60 years.
Bone: Justifications have normative extensions. If our
problem is purchaser confusion, when we probe the justification for
intervening, that can be extended into post-sale confusion. Then we package the
extension in terms of the doctrine.
Suddenly we have a confusion idea that has even further extension. Not easy to cabin by saying we just have one problem.
Cumulation of rights: transaction costs; uncertainty costs;
always costs from cumulation, but we might be more worried here if there is a
chill on innovation or creativity.
Doctrinal migration is also a cost.
Fair use in copyright à nominative use in TM. We might like that result, but
the phenomenon can have pernicious effect if not reasoned out at the level of
justification. All of that can happen
without conflict of rights.
Judges may be responding to other moral values as well. (Personality?) We have to respond to those in
a more direct way—respond to the affirmative case for protection as well as to
the defenses.
McKenna: what we are talking about now as defenses or
limitations are deeply informed by what we think of as the natural boundary of
the right itself. If you look at most of the older cases we now think of as “defenses”
they are mostly telling you that TM is limited and doesn’t implicate the thing
at issue. Problem: TM doesn’t limit itself in that way any more, and we still
need ways to explain why certain behavior is ok. (Compare the evolution of fair use and Folsom v. March.) We allocate burdens so that some things look
like defenses, but basically nothing in TM works as a defense that trumps the
right—all the defenses have a caveat that confusion matters (other than perhaps
the strong form of Traffix).
Heymann: Can’t recharacterize defamation as IIED because you’re
evading defamation doctrine. We’re going to make sure the same First Amendment
limitations apply. If that is
instructive here, we need to think about the overarching limiting principle you’re
doing an end run around, and whether that necessarily has to be of
constitutional magnitude to be a backstop, or whether that can be defined in
terms of what the tort is about. Dastar is an example: the Court reads cases
about right to copy as being a right without attribution, even though that wasn’t
present before. Worries about creating
rules that are categorical because of the ways in which, for example, the
satire/parody distinction has been employed categorically.
Dinwoodie: doctrinal creep in both directions. Dastar
is a good example. Why? The facts are very defendant-favorable.
How do you fix a preference between two regimes? If copyright/patent conflicts with TM, we’ve
pretty much assumed that TM loses. Grey
goods: is that an example of where you want the TM rule to prevail
instead? The ECJ has said: if you can do
it under TM, you have to be able to do it under copyright? Even if you say that copyright/patent defines
the negative space, then which is it?
What happens if it’s not patentable but is copyrightable? Is negative space defined by novelty or by
originality?
McGeveran: sometimes we love doctrinal migration. Many people have proposed porting materiality
from false advertising to TM (I would say “back to TM”), and other things. It’s
not tidiness for tidiness’ sake. It’s not that movement of doctrines across is
bad. Sometimes there’s an underlying normative instinct.
Sheff: scope of competition is just different, which is why
copyright/patent prevail over TM. If the
issue is use of info, we’d be particularly concerned over other claims to
control that info. TM is second-order
info. So when you come to a TM-based claim directed as info as info, such as
how to build a street sign or Eisenhower’s biography, you implicate concerns
about how that info gets disseminated in a way that’s not necessarily TM’s
prerogative. (Does that address the grey
goods issue?)
Austin: question about which set of rights is superior is
partly about framing. Dastar: sometimes it’s difficult to
point to a public interest served by mislabeling—valuable info may be denied in
that instance. But if the frame is
broader and we see Dastar as a cipher
for broader issues about copyright owners dictating to others about how they go
to market, there’s a problem of ambush.
Fox was able to sit back and say “you didn’t provide this information that you should’ve.”
Kur: Dastar from
the European point of view. The problem
isn’t that TM doesn’t recognize attribution, but that from European point of
view there’s insufficient authorship. After copyright terminates, from the German
point of view it would be natural to accept that TM identifies the commercial
source and does not in addition give authorship attribution.
Copyright is often stronger because of its moral rights. We
do recognize parodies, though! Examples
of use of copyright: Swedish copyright used to prevent sales of lamps
throughout Europe. Maybe need a catalog
of basic user rights that cut through all categories. Parody; first sale; maybe some others.
Dinwoodie: easier to construct from the back end by defining
what def’ts can do rather than by carving them out of four different regimes.
Dogan: those two approaches can work in tandem. If you persuade courts of the social value of
the use, then various doctrinal tools can promote them.
Margreth Barrett: why do we have a pecking order? In US, it’s patent, copyright, and then TM.
In each case we say that they balance a particular interest (incentive/efficient
market) against competition as the one constant. Makes sense then to think of right to
copy/public domain as having a single shape.
RT: maybe the Omega
district court result—finding copyright misuse used to prevent grey market
watches—isn’t a reversal of the copyright/TM hierarchy, but an application of
Sheff’s principle. This isn’t really a copyrighted work you’re selling, it’s an
underlying good, and as such copyright isn’t even applicable.
Litman: change in how goods are sold has caused the question
of what’s being sold to get ever blurrier.
T-shirt: world’s best father, with a drawing of Darth Vader making
waffles. People have differing views
about whether George Lucas ought to control the existence of these shirts. If
we don’t take that into account, it’s hard to persuade. So how do we channel
that impulse? Maybe by identifying
liability-negating behavior. No reasonable person would look at that and say it
must be a Lucasfilm shirt—except some people do. (And Lucasfilm did
license a similar product!) Maybe
encouraging disclaimers could help.
Heymann: may also have similar conflicts when two people
assert rights in the same object: Snoopy is subject to a copyright, and also to
MetLife’s use as a mark. Gershwin’s
music: copyright for Gershwin estate and trademark for JetBlue. What happens when the copyright expires? What if the license isn’t exclusive? Is the exercise of a copyright now TM
infringement or contributory infringement?
(Marilyn Monroe/Marilyn Merlot photos situation.) This isn’t one entity claiming lots of
rights, but two with potential conflicts and a different kind of boundary
issue.
Dinwoodie: speaks to the importance of resisting categorical
rules.
Bently: have UK cases of this; some have got round this by
reallocating ownership of copyright in cases of “abuse.” Court constructs an implicit assignment of
the copyright. The case he’s thinking of
involved a work created to be a logo.
McKenna: picking up on Sheff’s idea, we don’t have to be
concerned with the social functions of TM because that’s not the business of
the law; we are just interested with source identification.
Sheff: those social values may have informational value we
may want to protect in other ways notwithstanding source identification.
Dinwoodie: you seem to be saying that info itself is more
important than second-order info which is valuable only insofar as it gives you
information about something else that has social value.
Sheff: yes.
Bone: but why? It’s all info.
Sheff: because the second-order info can be found in other
ways, and the first-order info can’t.
McKenna: Rhapsody in
Blue: easy to see that the use of the creative work is designating the
source of something other than itself. In many cases that distinction is pretty
elusive. Imagine if you could avoid Dastar
if you simply pled that your material designates the source of the
videotapes. In that case Dastar is meaningless. What if it were the case that other people
could use Snoopy in ads when he entered the public domain? Well, then you’d give people an incentive not
to use characters as TMs. There would be
transition costs, but okay.
Dogan: Fair point, but not all that realistic. We might see emerging, as we do in right of
publicity, a division in commercial/noncommercial uses. As Goldman pointed out with the LV basketball
case, courts may simply say it’s not right to use this in an ad. That might not be right/principled, but they’re
likely to do it. The courts are trying
to use commercial speech as the dividing line.
(As Dogan recognizes, while I fully concede the descriptive validity of
this account, I think it’s a defiance of the supposed contours of commercial
speech doctrine, which in every other
area purports to draw a distinction between false/misleading commercial
speech and truthful commercial speech, and the stuff being regulated here falls
on the latter side without being subjected to Central Hudson scrutiny as it in theory should be; this blind spot
comes, I think, from the fetishization of goodwill/property thinking.)
Sheff: Coase Theorem: what role private ordering plays in
resolving boundary disputes. Where private parties have allocated the rights
that might arise under various IP regimes between them, do we respect
that? Coase would say yes, with
implications for the private ordering we expect going forward. We’d expect
Schultz etc. to reserve all sorts of rights to do stuff with Snoopy; otherwise
MetLife would be willing to pay for more rights to prevent exercise of
copyright rights. (But then when the copyright expires that deal has to end at
least as to the public, as McKenna points out.)
Heymann: theoretically, what’s the big deal about letting
the logos survive as advertising as long as there’s protection for expressive
uses?
No comments:
Post a Comment