Monday, May 11, 2015

Reading list: entertainment franchises and Drassinower

Law and Creativity in the Age of the Entertainment Franchise, ed. Kathy Bowrey & Michael Handler: A collection of essays on the general theme, some much more specific than others. The editors suggest that the things that the entertainment industry values dont map very well onto the law, but that industry members nonetheless deploy/interact with the law to get what they want.  I like their working definition of franchises: franchises involve connected cultural content that some entity tries to exploit and keep profitable over time.
 
David Lindsay contributes a pretty bad defense of copyright in Franchises, imaginary worlds, authorship and fandom, arguing that a hierarchy of ownership is important to sustain the attractiveness of a cultural artifact, because fandoms are like religions and religions need hierarchyyes, multiple interpretations are inevitable, but polysemous meaning needs a claim of authoritativeness against which to define itself.  (I was not aware of that, and nor I think were the directors of many a Hamlet I have seen.  Polysemous meaning may well need other interpretations against which to define itself, but I see no requisite connection to hierarchy.)  In a world where different kinds of content compete for limited attention, he argues, its important to have a combination of material that is familiar to an audienceboth in terms of its content and its authorial reputationwith the potential for the generation of new meanings.  These universes must be owned to ensure their authenticity and integrity, without which fans and audiences wont form an ongoing attachment.  (Citation needed.)  Within those controlled boundaries, then, theres room for experimentation/playing out the rules of the world.  But fans need to be kept in line: Just as the ambiguous line between orthodoxy and heresy played a policing role in the Middle Ages, uncertainty surrounding copyright infringement is essential in constructing the terms of the relationship between franchise owners and online communities.  (Or not: see, e.g., transformativeworks.org.  I really wish people wouldnt treat copyright uncertainty as so much more uncertain than other legal regimes.  What does it take to avoid driving a car negligently?) 
 
The fact that franchise owners naturally have a strong interest in being a source (although not necessarily the sole source) of canonical meaning, and in being perceived by a fan community as the responsible (and potentially responsive) guardians (or co-guardians) of canonical meaning really says nothing about what the law should give them.  These claims for the necessity of some permanent meaning in order to preserve a community around a work have been made many times before; Ive never been persuaded. Lindsay even discusses affirmational v. transformative fandom, then proceeds to ignore transformative fandom by saying that fan communities are based upon defining themselves against outsiders,’” and therefore that fan communities do not protect the diversity of responses to texts but rather foster exclusion and identity politics, based on claims about their depth of knowledge (and loyalty to) canonical meaning and the enclosure of meaning.  He might feel excluded from my fandoms, but I am sure that none of them are recognizable in this description.
 
Of course fan/producer relations arent as simple as the contrast between franchise owners as over-zealous control freaks, and fans as the virtuous creators of socially valuable meaning, but thats not where fan studies is (or really has been for a while, if it ever was--he misses the whole aspect of fan studies that is about recuperating fandom from the pathologization to which it was subject and to which Lindsay seems to be indifferent).  A key issue is exploitation, and Lindsay just valorizes it instead of critiquing it or attempting to understand the many ways in which it might play out.  Its not helpful to insist that [i]n a commercial culture, content is a commodity and that economic law demands that producers maximize profitsnot only is it empirically false (theres plenty of irrational behavior in the content sector, not to mention noncommercial production), its normatively bankrupt. 
 
What really galls me is the evidence-free insistence that control is necessary to preserve something called authenticity, as if authenticity werent contingent and negotiable.  Lindsay even seems to acknowledge this, retreating to the assertion that struggles over authenticity are necessary to a franchisewhich gets us back to the religion point.  It may well be true that such struggles are a part of a healthy belief system, but that doesnt mean that there needs to be any state-sponsored religion.  When you have to analogize copyright law to the Inquisition, you might be on the wrong side of the argument.  (Really!  [J]ust as when the uniform Christian world view began to fray in the face of the proliferation of meanings spurred by the Reformation the Church developed institutions such as the Inquisition to police heretics, so, in the face of the proliferation of meanings through online fan communities, the threat of copyright infringement can be used by franchise owners to police meaning.)  I suppose its not surprising that the chapter lacks any concrete examples of how he thinks this works.  Lindsay refuses to define the extent of legal control he thinks is necessaryshall corporate owners wield the power of excommunication? What does it even mean to require a threat to hang over fan activities?  Must that threat ever be carried out?  Enforcement is absent in this accountthough it definitely wasnt in his analogous Inquisition.
 
More gems: Hierarchy is important: the creative process, and the relationship between authors and audiences, is necessarily asymmetrical . [E]veryone may be a creator, but that does not mean that everyone is equally creative.  (Straw men, anyone?)  GRRM doesnt like fan fiction, which means something.  But Lindsay doesnt want to enter into the increasingly tendentious debates over the pros and cons of fan fiction.  Still, if we feel sympathy for an author who feels sad over the bowdlerization of her creation by a corporate licensee, why wouldnt we feel the same sympathy when it is digitally empowered fans that may be responsible for the bowdlerizing?  (Id love to find this corner of fandom that bowdlerizes.  Of course, Congress has legalized what CleanFlicks, which really did bowdlerize, sought to do, so again I must wonder about relevance.) 
 
Really, Lindsay just wants to be clear that neither side, corporate or fandom, has self-evidently better claims to higher normative ground.  In this environment, its claims by individual authors like GRRM for respect that might be the most desirable, because they can disrupt both fandom and corporate constructions.  Why this ability to intervene in debates over meaning requires the threat of copyright infringement liability is an exercise left for the reader.
 
Johnson Okpaluba contributes a chapter on digital sampling, arguing that licensing was prevalent in the US music industry even before litigation established a rule of get a license or dont sample. Its true that its hard/impossible now to make commercial sample-heavy albums like Pauls Boutique and It Takes a Nation of Millions to Hold Us Back, but those werent ever the most common uses of sampling, Okpaluba argues, and those albums shouldnt be seen as an artistic peak, since thats just a subjective aesthetic judgment.  (Valuing the possibility of variety isnt part of this analysis.)  Producers shifted to new sampling techniques and/or live instrumentation, so legal constraints on sampling were productive of creativity.  Joseph Fishman recently made the same argument in Creating Around Copyright. I find it unpersuasive, since this thesis doesnt explain why the law is needed on top of artistic motives to experiment and strike out in new directions, and the resulting legal suppression is not neutral. 
 
David Rolphs chapter on defamation law and celebrities has an interesting case study of how filing a defamation case harmed the public image of a celebrity, turning him from nice guy into perceived bully.  Celebritys fluidity, Rolph suggests, may be inconsistent with defamation laws understanding of the stolidity of reputation.
 
Other chapters cover the Disneyfication of theater; Australian film and TV practices relating to reality show (and other) concepts; the codification of flamenco music; arts festivals; and carnivals as franchise opportunities for locations with communities with a strong connection to the Caribbean.  I didnt know that you can buy a carnival-in-a-box package to promote tourism to your city!
 
Abraham Drassinower, Whats Wrong with Copying?: Really thought-provoking book that proceeds from the thesis that copyright ought to be a true authors right: a right to participate in a conversation, which entails a like right of others, thus creating its own inherent limits (specifically the idea/expression distinction and transformative fair use).  Also, because copyright rights involve communication, non-usesincluding database uses and private copyingare not infringements of the legitimate copyright rights.  I was about half persuaded.  He convincingly argues that the balance metaphor of copyright (balancing author and audience interests) doesnt justify copyright because it doesnt tell us what is to be balanced.  It makes copyrights lack of coverage for ideas and facts, as well as fair use, into empirical questions when they shouldnt be; balancing certainly cant tell you as a matter of first principle that copyright should protect expression and only expression, or why copyright and patent are different. A mousetrap may well involve creativity just not the kind of creativity copyright protects.
 
He makes a good point about defending the public interest versus the public domain; instrumentalist accounts of copyright focus on the former, when we should defend the latter. In Drassinowers view, only understanding copyright as dealing with communicative acts can explain copyright: copyright is not a property right, but a right inhering in persons as speaking beings.  Because others need free access to ideas and transformative fair use, an authors claim cant extend to thosethough Drassinower doesnt fully convince me that hes defended these needs (why is freedom to copy ideas always necessary to the next author?). 
 
One quibble comes from his use of Borges Pierre Menard, Author of the Quixote to defend the principle that independent creation cant be infringement, since Menard is definitely an authorbut Menard was also definitely not an independent creator in the sense of not needing Cervantes as a but-for cause of his creation.  I also thought his distinction between copyright and trademark was unpersuasive, since he defines trademark as the right to completely control the meaning of a mark as applied to a good or service, and a trademark is not and should not be that!  Were allowed to talk about a Mickey Mouse operation, or a Cadillac health plan. 
 
As Drassinower recognizes, entailed in his view is that the derivative works right is illegitimate, which would be a big changethough he does allow for room for infringement via substantial similarity, at least in some cases.  He also, in what I think is a concession thats inconsistent with his theory but he thinks necessary for practical purposes, allows for the existence of a translation right.  Of course translation also requires creative endeavor by the translator, but he argues that [u]nlike fan fiction, which uses the work of another in ones own, translation is not a speaking in ones own words but a rendering of anothers words in another language. Unauthorized translation is therefore infringing. Im not sure I can go with himwhy isnt then a movie version a translation of a book into a different medium and therefore infringing, justifying at least part of the derivative works right?  He recognizes translation as authorial but also infringing; that opens the possibility of other categories of authorial acts that are also infringing, and now were back to fighting over the scope of the derivative works right.
 
Drassinower is trenchant in his criticism of US parochialism, which dismisses rights-based accounts of copyright law out of hand.  Low-protectionists worry that an author-centered account of copyright would give authors too much control, but not all authorial demands would be plausible in his accountrespecting an authors autonomy doesnt require us to diminish the autonomy of others.  Only republishing her words without also transforming them to be ones own expression, whether through commentary or otherwise, ought to count as compelled speech (treating her like a puppet, working at the behest of others without her consent) that she can suppress.

No comments:

Post a Comment