In light of recent discussions about Glee's cover of Jonathan Coulton's arrangement of Baby Got Back, have some Rockabye Baby, offering lullaby covers of Rush, the Smiths, etc. Has the fundamental character of Tom Sawyer been changed? What about Girlfriend in a Coma? (For what it's worth, this type of cover is why I've always assumed that there is in practice essentially nothing that changes the basic melody or fundamental character of a work for purposes of the cover right.)
HT Zach Schrag.
Wednesday, January 30, 2013
Tuesday, January 29, 2013
Terminator Too: Judgment Play
From the creator of Point Break Live, fresh from a court victory finding that her interactive retelling of the Kathryn Bigelow/Keanu Reeves movie was a fair use and thus that another theater couldn't use her script even with a license from the owners of the copyright in the Bigelow/Reeves original, comes this gem, which almost makes me wish I were in LA to see it.
Monday, January 28, 2013
reading list: Coding Freedom
E. Gabriella Coleman, Coding Freedom: The Ethics and Aesthetics of Hacking: Free download available.
Coleman argues that free/open source software forms a kind of lifeworld for programmers deeply embedded in it, which provides a source of pleasure (and frustration) as well as a very limited kind of politics that seeks effectiveness from being deliberately unconnected to other kinds of politics. Hackers meld commitments to free speech and individualism with deeply embodied pleasure in losing themselves in coding and collective action in service of self-chosen goals: “a liberal politics of free speech and liberty that speaks to an audience beyond hackers as well as a nonliberal politics of cultural pleasure and political detachment, which is internally and intensely focused on the practice of hacking only and entirely for its own sake, although certainly inspiring others to follow in their footsteps.” They endorse liberal ideals while also valuing unalienated labor (often enough in their off hours, working for The Man during the day).
Random thoughts: I had no idea that Unix got its name from “eunuchs,” describing that it had been “cut down” from a previous OS, Multics. I was struck by the commonality of fannish language/commitments, such as the deep enjoyment of conventions that bring together people who usually only communicate online, or the developer who said:
What’s interesting about Coleman’s explanation, though I have no doubt she’s accurately reporting how hackers experienced the legal encounter, is that they were working not in a right-answer area but, in wording licenses, regularly confronted the legal ambiguities that are also bog-standard in law. For example, the popular Creative Commons Noncommercial license doesn’t define “noncommercial,” and it turns out that its users are deeply divided on what that might mean; e pur se muove.
Thus, I’m even more struck by Coleman’s observation that, while learning the law often leads to cynicism among hackers and non-hackers, hackers weren’t frustrated by the process of learning in the way non-hackers often are. I take it that they felt that the apparent arcana weren’t all that different from the specialized language and language-rules they already learned. But taken too seriously, that treatment of law as code in the sense of computer code leads to people deciding that the income tax is unconstitutional, or that they can’t be tried in courts that display flags with fringes on them, or that they can copyright their own names. Still, most people end up understanding that there’s more than one way to do things in law, and that input and output are not solely determined by the language of a statute or contract.
Coleman addresses the spread of F/OSS, which she argues was enabled by hackers’ refusal to engage with standard conservative or liberal ideologies, avoiding polarization and ghettoization. And yet that goes only so far. Of Larry Lessig, she says, “Part of [Lessig’s] success can be attributed to the fact that he, like F/OSS geeks, is reluctant to portray his work as political; instead, he prefers to articulate his position either in terms of a constitutionality that sits above the fray of politics or in terms of the importance of cultural preservation.” Except not really! Lessig recognized the severe limits of that strategy post-Eldred, when he made an explicitly political turn and proclaimed that there will be no real legal improvement, in copyright or otherwise, without reform of the process of buying elections.
Indeed, to me, Coleman’s discussion of Lessig skirts the trap she so clearly identifies: the idea that online production can happen without organization/institutions, which as she says was an attractive meme because it “perfectly meshes with, and thus supports, dominant understandings of freedom, agency, and individualism.” She specifically points to Clay Shirky’s Here Comes Everybody, with its subtitle The Power of Organizing without Organizations. “Although many of his observations about digital dynamics are illuminating, and many of the examples he draws on, such as meet-up groups, remain informal, many others that he discusses, such as Wikipedia and Linux, were by 2006, organized, and as such, some type of organization.”
I’d extend this to politics: at some point, if you want your organization to work, you have to get in the game, and that means showing up in political contexts, whether that’s before an administrative agency, in court, or before Congress. And open source organizations have done so—litigating in the US and other countries to enforce an open source license; participating in Brazil’s attempt to go officially open source, etc. (Obviously I have an agenda here too—not for nothing is it the “Organization for Transformative Works.”) Coleman explains how certain kinds of organizations can maintain that they don’t fit along the Right/Left axis, and thus that they aren’t political, but as she notes, the “and thus” is itself a political claim, and not ultimately a very convincing one (to me; she leaves this to the reader).
Random thoughts: I had no idea that Unix got its name from “eunuchs,” describing that it had been “cut down” from a previous OS, Multics. I was struck by the commonality of fannish language/commitments, such as the deep enjoyment of conventions that bring together people who usually only communicate online, or the developer who said:
What really grabbed me was the community. That was what really grabbed me, and you have to understand at the time, it was a completely foreign notion. [ . . . ] I had stumbled on this group of people that were interested in the same things that I was interested in that had, basically for no particular reason, built this thing, this operating system, and it actually worked, and I could do my work in it and I had not paid a dime for it; they did not ask anything of me when I downloaded it or used it.Coleman also discusses the different political orientations at work, comparing Eric Raymond’s desire to make open source compatible with the business world to Richard Stallman’s anticapitalism. Raymond argued that economic success would “allow [hackers] to reap enough social capital so that they could escape a cultural ghetto of marginalized nerdiness.” Meanwhile, a conflict with copyright as it had been understood was brewing, and open source partisans had to learn how to articulate legal arguments as they attacked copyright control, wrote their own licenses, and turned copyright back on itself to preserve the openness of their work through open source licensing. Here Coleman posits a particular orientation towards legal interpretation, arguing that
the skills, mental dispositions, and forms of reasoning necessary to read and analyze a formal, rule-based system like the law parallel the operations necessary to code software. Both, for example, are logic oriented, internally consistent textual practices that require great attention to detail. Small mistakes in both law and software— a missing comma in a contract or a missing semicolon in code— can jeopardize the system’s integrity and compromise the author’s intention.But this is not nearly as true in law as it is in software—computers are so dumb that they only do what you tell them, but humans, including judges and other legal actors, have intentionality. They are capable of doing what you meant them to do, especially if that’s consistent with other commitments they have. And in DMCA cases, one of Coleman’s case studies, several courts have done exactly that, refusing to apply the DMCA to attempts to control markets for garage door openers and printer toner cartridges even though the language of the law on its face would cover them because they contain copyrighted works. Nor do many laws—say, for example, what constitutes a derivative work or even boundary cases of fair use—have the clean edges of things like copyright duration, where there is in fact a right answer independent of one’s other commitments (albeit an answer that’s often aggravatingly hard to come by).
What’s interesting about Coleman’s explanation, though I have no doubt she’s accurately reporting how hackers experienced the legal encounter, is that they were working not in a right-answer area but, in wording licenses, regularly confronted the legal ambiguities that are also bog-standard in law. For example, the popular Creative Commons Noncommercial license doesn’t define “noncommercial,” and it turns out that its users are deeply divided on what that might mean; e pur se muove.
Thus, I’m even more struck by Coleman’s observation that, while learning the law often leads to cynicism among hackers and non-hackers, hackers weren’t frustrated by the process of learning in the way non-hackers often are. I take it that they felt that the apparent arcana weren’t all that different from the specialized language and language-rules they already learned. But taken too seriously, that treatment of law as code in the sense of computer code leads to people deciding that the income tax is unconstitutional, or that they can’t be tried in courts that display flags with fringes on them, or that they can copyright their own names. Still, most people end up understanding that there’s more than one way to do things in law, and that input and output are not solely determined by the language of a statute or contract.
Coleman addresses the spread of F/OSS, which she argues was enabled by hackers’ refusal to engage with standard conservative or liberal ideologies, avoiding polarization and ghettoization. And yet that goes only so far. Of Larry Lessig, she says, “Part of [Lessig’s] success can be attributed to the fact that he, like F/OSS geeks, is reluctant to portray his work as political; instead, he prefers to articulate his position either in terms of a constitutionality that sits above the fray of politics or in terms of the importance of cultural preservation.” Except not really! Lessig recognized the severe limits of that strategy post-Eldred, when he made an explicitly political turn and proclaimed that there will be no real legal improvement, in copyright or otherwise, without reform of the process of buying elections.
Indeed, to me, Coleman’s discussion of Lessig skirts the trap she so clearly identifies: the idea that online production can happen without organization/institutions, which as she says was an attractive meme because it “perfectly meshes with, and thus supports, dominant understandings of freedom, agency, and individualism.” She specifically points to Clay Shirky’s Here Comes Everybody, with its subtitle The Power of Organizing without Organizations. “Although many of his observations about digital dynamics are illuminating, and many of the examples he draws on, such as meet-up groups, remain informal, many others that he discusses, such as Wikipedia and Linux, were by 2006, organized, and as such, some type of organization.”
I’d extend this to politics: at some point, if you want your organization to work, you have to get in the game, and that means showing up in political contexts, whether that’s before an administrative agency, in court, or before Congress. And open source organizations have done so—litigating in the US and other countries to enforce an open source license; participating in Brazil’s attempt to go officially open source, etc. (Obviously I have an agenda here too—not for nothing is it the “Organization for Transformative Works.”) Coleman explains how certain kinds of organizations can maintain that they don’t fit along the Right/Left axis, and thus that they aren’t political, but as she notes, the “and thus” is itself a political claim, and not ultimately a very convincing one (to me; she leaves this to the reader).
calculation of remedies and vicarious liability under California consumer protection law
People v. JTH Tax, Inc., -- Cal. Rptr. 3d --, 2013 WL 177140
(Cal. App. 1 Dist.)
JTH, doing business as Liberty Tax Service, unsuccessfully
appealed from a large judgment against it, awarding the people of the state of
California about $1.169 million in civil penalties, ordering Liberty to pay roughly
$135,000 in restitution, and permanently enjoining Liberty in several ways for
violating state and federal lending, unfair competition, consumer protection,
and false advertising laws. I won’t
discuss the federal Truth In Lending Act claims.
Liberty provides tax preparation and related loan services (refund
anticipation loans and “electronic refund checks”), with 195 franchised stores
in California, and two company-owned stores during part of the relevant period,
all doing business as Liberty Tax Service.
The AG’s lawsuit claimed that Liberty and its franchisees made
misleading or deceptive statements in ads, and also had inadequate disclosures
on Liberty’s RAL and ERC applications about various costs/risks to
consumers. Liberty made a lot of money
from RALs and ERCs, including in California; it got percentages or flat fees
from the banks with which it worked, and RALs and ERCs also cross-subsidized
its tax preparation services, which was important because many of its customers
couldn’t afford to pay for them out of pocket.
The trial court found that Liberty’s handling fee charged to
ERC customers was an undisclosed finance charge in violation of TILA (since an
ERC was a form of credit allowing delayed payment for tax preparation
services), and that the failure to disclose this also violated the UCL and FAL.
Second, the trial court found that using “cross-collection” to collect tax
refund loan debts from prior transactions, including non-Liberty transactions,
was deceptive, unfair, and illegal.
(This could occur when consumers’ prior RALs were larger than the
refunds they ultimately received; because a RAL was a loan, they remained potentially
liable on the debt.) Third, the trial
court found that certain print and TV ads were likely to deceive within the
meaning of the UCL and FAL; Liberty was liable for its own ads and those placed
by California franchisees. Among other
things, Liberty was enjoined from directly or indirectly representing a RAL as
an actual refund, and from failing to state conspicuously that the product is a
loan and including the name of the lending institution and the fee or interest
it will charge.
The court of appeals upheld the determination that Liberty’s
cross-collection practices violated multiple state laws along with the federal
Fair Debt Collection Practices Act (FDCPA).
Liberty waived its arguments about the fraudulent and unfair prongs of the
UCL and about the FAL, so the court didn’t need to reach other bases for
liability. Liberty was responsible for
bringing customers to the banks, soliciting loan applications and getting
consumers to sign applications that authorized cross-collection. These authorizations covered any unpaid RAL
debts, whether owed to Liberty or to anyone else, and whether the debt was
stale or otherwise uncollectable. The
trial court found that both unsophisticated and reasonable consumers were
unlikely to recall the details of such debts, particularly those “incurred far
in the past and perhaps in connection with a loan issued by a different lender
and/or obtained through a different tax preparer.” Consumers had no meaningful notice of whether
there was a claim against them before they authorized the cross-collection;
they thus lost the right to dispute the debt, and thus the practice was
deceptive, unfair, and in violation of the FDCPA. The cross-collection authorization “appeared
on the second or third pages of lengthy and complex contracts that on their
face had nothing to do with debt collection, making it unlikely that applicants
would read and understand the significance of the information.”
The trial court found that Liberty had wrongly attempted to
collect an extant debt as to 118 customers from 2002 to 2005 and imposed
$118,000 in civil penalties under the UCL and FAL, given that the violations
were serious, persistent, and long-standing.
Even if Liberty’s construction of the state and federal FDCPA and the
CLRA were correct and its conduct was not “unlawful,” it didn’t address the
trial court’s finding that Liberty’s practices were fraudulent and unfair.
Liberty also challenged its liability for franchisee
advertising. The district court
explained that a franchisee can be a franchisor’s agent, depending on the
extent of the franchisor’s control.
Franchisors face “the Scylla of failing to exercise sufficient control
to protect their marks, and the Charybdis of exercising so much control they
are vicariously liable for the torts of the franchisees or other licensees.” (It’s not clear to me why this is Scylla and
Charybdis: in seeking the benefits of franchising, franchisors of course don’t
want to be responsible for their franchisees’ bad behavior, but why should the
legal system honor that desire while still deeming them in total control of
their marks?) Anyway, the trial court
determined that its agency inquiry had to focus on “the extent to which the
control reserved to the franchisor plainly exceeds that required to police the
mark, which is control so pervasive that it amounts to complete or substantial
control over the daily activities of the franchisee's business.”
This was the right standard.
Though a couple of other cases have said that “vicarious liability”
isn’t available in an action for unfair business practices, the key case with
that language involved only “reverse vicarious liability,” meaning that
“officers and directors are not automatically (vicariously) liable for the acts
of the company that employs them.”
The trial court pointed to Liberty’s operations manual,
which showed a right of control far in excess of that needed to police the
mark:
Liberty required franchisees to
offer RAL's and ERC's via banks mandated by Liberty; prohibited franchisees from
offering products and services without Liberty's permission; mandated
franchisees' minimum operating hours, computers to be used, and day-to-day
tasks such as how to open the store and when to clean the bathrooms; reserved
the right to intervene in disputes with customers, including the right to pay
refunds directly to customers and bill the franchisees for them; required
franchisees to commit to maintaining Liberty's prescribed filing system and the
setup for the tax return processing center; and controlled franchisee pricing
by controlling the discounts franchisees could offer at different times of the
year.
The trial court also emphasized Liberty's “particularly
extensive” right of control over franchisee advertising, which Liberty used to
not only protect its marks, “but also to dictate business strategy to
franchisees.” For example, it controlled
discounts because of its beliefs about customers’ price sensitivity over time,
and barred certain advertising as “a waste of time and money.” The operation manuals provided detailed
advertising instructions divided by time of year; mandated extensive
pre-approval; and provided samples. Liberty
was “literally providing a detailed, step-by-step guide for every aspect of
marketing and advertising.” Further, Liberty retained an open-ended right to
modify the manual without franchisees’ consent; its essentially complete
control over operations, specifically over advertising, exceeded that
reasonably necessary to protect the mark.
Thus, at least for purposes of advertising, Liberty’s franchisees were
its agents.
As a result, Liberty was responsible for more than 100
illegal ads by Liberty franchisees, including 43 ads that falsely promised
“most refunds in one day” or a variation on that theme, including four specifically
approved by Liberty, and 67 ads that unlawfully omitted mandatory bank name and
lender fee disclosures.
The court of appeals approved the trial court’s
reasoning. Liberty argued that it didn’t
exercise day-to-day operational control and that franchisees were solely
responsible for training, hiring, firing, and supervising their employees;
outfitting their offices; complying with all laws; and choosing how many
offices to operate. They also had
discretion to select among marketing methods, design ads subject to Liberty’s
approval, and pick a marketing budget.
This wasn’t enough to save Liberty under California law; it wasn’t
essential that the right of control be exercised or that the principal actually
supervise the agent’s work. The
existence of the right established the agency relationship.
It was true that the franchisor-franchisee relationship
allows certain controls to protect the franchisor’s marks and goodwill without
transforming the relationship into one of agency. But it was also true that the franchisor’s
“unique interests” don’t remove agency liability “if the franchisor exercises a
right of control that goes beyond its interests in its marks and goodwill.”
This was a question of fact, and the trial court articulated the correct
standard. Since there was substantial
evidence to support its findings, they would not be disturbed.
Liberty required preapproval of all ads, which it used not
just to protect its marks and goodwill but also to control business strategies
and tactics; there was evidence that it rejected certain ads for being
inconsistent with its pricing strategies.
The trial court specifically found that Liberty controlled RAL- and
ERC-related ads and disclosures.
Rejecting ads because it was “good for business,” as Liberty argued,
wasn’t coextensive with “protecting the goodwill in its mark.” The court of
appeals wouldn’t reweigh the trial court’s conclusions.
In another case, the California Supreme Court suggested in
dicta that a Ford dealer might not be responsible for a salesperson’s false
statement if it showed that “it made every effort to discourage
misrepresentations; had no knowledge of salespeople's misleading statements; and,
when so informed, refused to accept the benefits of any sales based on
misrepresentations and took action to prevent a reoccurrence.” Liberty argued that it qualified for this
“exception,” but the discussion in the Ford
case indicated that this was a question of fact for the trial court, and the
undisputed facts did not show that Liberty made “every effort” to discourage misrepresentations.
Though its manual prohibited use in any advertising of the
phrases “instant refund” or “refunds in 24 hours,” the evidence indicated that
Liberty became aware of the unapproved ads “sort [of] by happenstance” and
didn’t then put a system in place to monitor them, for example by checking
Pennysaver, the publication where the unapproved ads were showing up. There was evidence that it let the problem
slide for 2 years, while dozens of ads began appearing in Pennysaver that
improperly promised such things as “Most Refunds in One Day,” “Get $1200 in
Minutes ... And the Rest of Your Tax Refund in 24 Hours,” “Most Refunds in 24
Hours” and “Got W–2? 24 Hour Refunds.” After an early low-level contact with
Pennysaver failed, Liberty didn’t reach out to a senior executive until six
months after the AG found the illegal ads and two months before trial. Liberty argued that it took reasonable steps,
but that wasn’t what the Ford exception
would require, which was “every effort.”
The court of appeals then affirmed the civil penalties under
the UCL and FAL. The penalty for each
violation can’t exceed $2500 (though the UCL and FAL penalties are cumulative),
but what counts as a “violation” depends on the facts and circumstances. The
trial court’s ruling on this is reviewed for abuse of discretion. Each copy of a newspaper shouldn’t count as a
“violation,” because that could easily lead to outsize liabilities. But a single edition of a newspaper isn’t
necessarily, as a matter of law, a single violation either. Instead, a single publication constitutes a
minimum of one violation, with as many additional violations “as there are
persons who read the advertisement or who responded to the advertisement by
purchasing the advertised product or service or by making inquiries concerning
such product or service.” This is
reasonably related to the gain or opportunity achieved by disseminating a
deceptive ad. Expert testimony and
circumstantial evidence could provide the necessary proof. Other factors bearing on the determination
include whether the misrepresentations were intentional or negligent, the
medium’s circulation, the nature and extent of public injury, and the
advertiser’s size and wealth.
Liberty argued that the trial court imposed excessive
penalties based only on gross circulation for print publications and Nielsen
ratings for TV shows. However, the People’s
expert provided a reasonable basis for calculating how many people actually saw
the ads, and even for showing that viewers saw the deceptive ads multiple
times; the district court didn’t impose penalties for multiple viewings. Given that the ads aired 1829 times, the
maximum penalty could have been over $9 million; $715,344 was reasonable. Anyway, Liberty’s arguments would essentially
require proof of each individual who saw an illegal TV ad, which would defeat
the purpose of the civil penalty.
The court reasoned similarly with respect to penalties
imposed for Pennysaver ads mailed to homes.
The trial court didn’t rely on gross circulation figures, but used a
fraction of circulation as a proxy—here .0088 for Liberty-approved Pennysaver
ads, and .0044 for ads for which Liberty was vicariously liable. The resulting figure of nearly $1 million was
then reduced to $50,000 because the initial calculation was grossly
disproportionate to Liberty’s role and the harm inflicted. Still, there was circumstantial evidence to
support this penalty. Liberty’s
marketing department and its franchisees considered Pennysaver to be
particularly effective at reaching its target audience, and many of the illegal
ads appeared on the front cover, increasing the chances they’d be read. And Liberty didn’t provide a better means of
calculation.
The court of appeals also upheld the injunctive relief
ordered by the trial court, which was designed to “address Liberty's failures
not only to educate its own internal staff on the legalities of advertising,
but its failure in controlling its franchises.” Liberty was required to discipline employees
with escalating sanctions for violating the requirements, as well as to give
franchisees written warnings and order them to pay $15,000 fines to the AG for
a second violation, then terminate them for a third. It was further required to audit at least 10
California franchisees each year, monitor Pennysavers to make sure franchisees
are complying with the law, and notify California franchisees during tax season
reminding them of their obligations.
A court has the power to order “necessary” relief, and its
discretion is broad; the court of appeals found no abuse of that discretion
here. Liberty argued that a franchisee
that inadvertently violated the law once by using an insufficiently conspicuous
disclaimer, and then did so again 15 years later, could be required to pay the
fine. The court was unimpressed by this
speculation. Liberty also argued that it
didn’t have the contractual right to fine franchisees (and that the fine was
six times the penalty available for a single violation of the UCL or FAL).
But the trial court found that the violations were serious
and persistent. Liberty didn’t devote
enough resources to monitoring franchisee ads, even though it knew it had a
problem with unapproved and illegal ads in Pennysaver in particular. As to one illegal TV ad, Liberty’s chief marketing
officer testified that she’d still approve it for use in California. An injunction was needed to address Liberty’s
failure to educate its internal staff and its failure in controlling
franchisees.
Liberty complained about the permanence of the injunction,
but the court maintained jurisdiction.
Liberty could apply for modification or termination as appropriate.
Then, Liberty argued that the injunction didn’t give
reasonable notice of what conduct was prohibited because Liberty would have to
draw legal conclusions about whether a franchisee’s ad disclaimer was
“conspicuous.” But conspicuousness is a
requirement that provides sufficient notice, and a more specific order wouldn’t
be feasible, since conspicuousness can vary with an ad’s size, color, placement,
and design.
ambiguity of "authenticity" defeats literal falsity claim
Kwan Software Engineering, Inc. v. Foray Technologies, LLC,
2013 WL 244999 (N.D. Cal.)
Plaintiff, known as Veripic, moved to enjoin its competitor
Foray from making certain claims about its technology. It had copyright, DMCA, and related claims,
but only sought injunctive relief on its false advertising claims, which the
court denied.
Both parties make software for handling digital evidence for
police departments and similar entities.
Veripic sells the Digital Photo Lab (DPL) while Foray sells the
Authenticated Digital Asset Management System (ADAMS) software. ADAMS employs a hash function that allows a
user to validate whether digital evidence “has been manipulated or altered
between the time it is entered into the ADAMS software system and a later time
when a user wishes to make use of that piece of digital evidence.” Veripic has similar technology, but it also
allows users to validate whether the digital evidence has been altered from the
moment a picture was originally taken.
Basically, Veripic argued that Foray falsely advertised that
its software could “authenticate” images according to guidelines propounded by
the Scientific Working Group on Imaging Technology (SWGIT), when in fact it
could only guarantee “integrity.”
Authenticity, Veripic argued, required further validation of whether the
picture was an accurate depiction of the world (subject matter authenticity),
not just whether it had been altered once entered into the system (acquisition
authenticity).
This was a literal falsity claim only. The court therefore looked at the meaning of
“authenticity” as the term was understood by law enforcement customers and
others in the market for digital evidence management software, and found that
“integrity” and “authenticity” were “ambiguous, overlapping, and sometimes
interchangeable.” On the evidence before
the court, numerous relevant entities—including SWGIT and even Veripic—went
back and forth, sometimes distinguishing “authentication” from “integrity” and sometimes
using “authentication” to mean “integrity.”
Thus, Veripic didn’t show it was likely to succeed on the merits.
Veripic also complained of other statements, such as that
ADAMS was the only software that complied “with the SWGIT ‘requirement’
contained in the workflow described in Section 13, Best Practices for
Maintaining the Integrity of Digital Images and Digital Video of the SWGIT
Guidelines…. While some vendors may claim they are ASCLD or SWGIT compliant, no
other digital evidence management vendor complies with the SWGIT workflow # 2
[described in Section 13].”
The court found that this wasn’t literally false, even
though the workflow #2 was only an example and not required to comply with the
best practices. ADAMS used a series of
steps “known to be wanted or needed by the example workflow”—which fit the OED
definition of “requirement.” Moreover,
Veripic’s DPL could achieve a similar result, but not by complying with example
#2. Veripic “specifically eschewed” the
process set out in #2 as cumbersome and offered a different solution (though
one that also apparently complied with the best practices). So ADAMS literally
complies with example #2 and DPL doesn’t, and there was no threshold showing of
literal falsity.
Veripic also didn’t show irreparable harm, despite “a
speculative declaration from its company president in which he states that six
customers have told Veripic that it was their understanding that ‘Foray
authenticated digital images in the same manner as Veripic.’” First, Veripic
should have been aware of the alleged misrepresentations since at least June
2011, when Seattle made Foray’s RFP response available to Veripic; that
contained the offending statements. This
delay “hardly bespeaks of the urgency typical in successful preliminary
injunction motions.” Second, the court didn’t think the evidence showed
anything more than legitimate competition.
“In fact, most customers purchase one of these competing software suites
only after first reviewing responses to requests for proposals, company
presentations and extensive research.”
Lost customers might well be the result of full understanding and
preference for one product over the other.
Though the public interest in the integrity of law enforcement evidence
was great, the court was willing to rely on the sophisticated customers’ careful
investment in purchase decisions to protect it.
Do you know where your towel is, and what claims it gives rise to?
Hall v. Bed Bath & Beyond, Inc., --- F.3d ----, 2013 WL
276080 (Fed. Cir.)
Hall alleged that BBB engaged in false or misleading advertising by claiming that its towel has “performance that lasts the useful lifetime of the towel.” He claimed that he washed one of BBB’s towels and it was damaged after a single washing, and the district court observed that “the difference between the [once] washed product and new is noticeable.” However, the court then held that the advertising was puffery, not falsifiable, and that BBB “makes no guarantees about how long the towel itself will last.” Further, the district court found that Hall didn’t plausibly allege injury, to which Hall argued that the similar appearance would confuse consumers, who’d expect Hall's towel to be of similar poor quality. (Again, a trademark rationale, not a general false advertising rationale.)
Hall obtained a design patent on a “Tote Towel,” a large
towel with binding around all the edges, zippered pockets at both ends, and an
angled cloth loop in the middle. He
began producing the towel soon after filing his patent application. He had a meeting with Bed Bath & Beyond
and left samples of the packaged towel with BBB; both the package and the towel
were marked “patent pending.” BBB then
had copies of the towel made, and Hall sued for patent infringement, unfair
competition under the Lanham Act, and misappropriation under New York law. The district court dismissed the complaint on
the pleadings, and the Federal Circuit reversed except for the claims against
individual executives sued in their personal capacity.
Design patent: The district court ruled that the complaint
didn’t allege which aspects of the towel merited design patent protection, or
how the defendants infringed the claim.
All that was required was to allege ownership of a cited patent, state
the means by which each named defendant allegedly infringed, and point to the
sections of patent law invoked. BBB even
admitted in its motion to dismiss on other grounds that patent infringement was
pled properly. Claim construction isn’t
an essential element of a patent infringement claim.
The district court wanted the complaint to allege, among
other things, what about the towel was “‘new, original and ornamental,’ meriting the
protection of a design patent,” but that’s not required by Iqbal/Twombly to give fair notice of the claim. In any event, infringement is based on the
design as a whole, not any points of novelty; the design patent is infringed if
the ordinary observer would find them substantially the same/deceptively
similar.
Hall’s complaint identified the patent, included a picture, and described the accused towel as “virtually identical,” with the same shape and almost the same dimensions, including the “unique zippered compartments and hanging loop.” Hall alleged that the resemblance would deceive an ordinary observer, following the infringement standard. The record also included pictures including the two towels. The district court’s sua sponte dismissal should have been reserved for a complaint that was “so confused, ambiguous, vague, or otherwise unintelligible that its true substance, if any, is well disguised.” The pleadings allowed the court to draw the reasonable inference that BBB was liable; no more was required.
Hall’s complaint identified the patent, included a picture, and described the accused towel as “virtually identical,” with the same shape and almost the same dimensions, including the “unique zippered compartments and hanging loop.” Hall alleged that the resemblance would deceive an ordinary observer, following the infringement standard. The record also included pictures including the two towels. The district court’s sua sponte dismissal should have been reserved for a complaint that was “so confused, ambiguous, vague, or otherwise unintelligible that its true substance, if any, is well disguised.” The pleadings allowed the court to draw the reasonable inference that BBB was liable; no more was required.
Lanham Act: the district court found that the complaint
merely alleged unfair competition “without elaboration.” The court of appeals disagreed, based on the
following allegations:
¶ 62. Defendants' use of [phrases
including “Workout Towel,” “drapes around your neck,” and “convenient zipper
pockets”] are likely to cause confusion, mistake, or to deceive as to the
affiliation, connection, or association between the Tote Towel and the
Counterfeit Towel.
¶ 63. The packaging of the
Counterfeit Towel also states “performance that lasts the useful lifetime of
the towel.”...Defendants' use of these terms and words on its label and in
commercial advertising and promotion misrepresents the nature, characteristics,
and qualities of the Counterfeit Towel which is of extremely poor quality and
falls apart only after several washes.
¶ 64. Defendants' attempts to claim
Hall's innovations and sell inferior, cheaper products, promising lifetime use,
amount to unfair competition and misappropriation under The Lanham Act, 15 U.S
.C. § 1125(a), which has caused and continues to cause serious injury to
Plaintiff.
The district court held that the “likely to cause confusion”
allegation didn’t state a claim because the complaint didn’t allege the
existence of a trademark, either in the packaging or the design. On appeal, Hall argued that his complaint
wasn’t limited to trademark/trade dress, but rather that BBB advertised an
identical and similarly packaged towel that would be confused with Hall’s
towel. (Um, that is a trade dress claim. That’s like saying that two light bulbs are
indistinguishable and therefore confusing. See below for more.) A false
advertising claim can be brought against a defendant who misrepresents the
quality of its own goods.
Hall alleged that BBB engaged in false or misleading advertising by claiming that its towel has “performance that lasts the useful lifetime of the towel.” He claimed that he washed one of BBB’s towels and it was damaged after a single washing, and the district court observed that “the difference between the [once] washed product and new is noticeable.” However, the court then held that the advertising was puffery, not falsifiable, and that BBB “makes no guarantees about how long the towel itself will last.” Further, the district court found that Hall didn’t plausibly allege injury, to which Hall argued that the similar appearance would confuse consumers, who’d expect Hall's towel to be of similar poor quality. (Again, a trademark rationale, not a general false advertising rationale.)
The court of appeals concluded that Hall plausibly pleaded
falsity, whether literal or by necessary implication. Although “lasts the useful lifetime of the
towel” literally just says that the towel lasts as long as it lasts, even if it
lasts for only one washing, that could still be false. The claim “implies that
the towel will not fall apart after a single wash or a few washes.…A reasonable
consumer would expect the ‘useful lifetime’ of a towel to be more than one or a
few washes.” The court analogized to the
“Night Time Strength” case, Novartis Consumer Health, Inc. v. Johnson & Johnson–Merck Consumer Pharmaceuticals Co., 290 F.3d 578 (3d Cir. 2002). While in
theory “Night Time Strength” could mean “whatever strength the product happened
to have at night,” the court there found falsity by necessary implication
because the phrase conveyed that the product was specially made to work at
night.
Nor did Hall need to plead actual harm, only likely
harm. The parties’ products compete, and
Hall alleged that one of his resale customers mistakenly believed that BBB was
selling Hall's towel “for nearly half his price.” When the parties compete and
the advertising is misleading, dismissal on the pleadings was inappropriate,
given the Lanham Act’s “flexible approach” to injury and causation.
The district court thought that the performance claim was
nonactionable puffery. The test was whether a reasonable buyer would take the
representation at face value; if no one would take it seriously, there’d be no
danger of consumer deception. BBB’s claim
of “lasting” performance was “stated as a fact; it is not ‘blustering’ or ‘boasting,’
and does not sound like ‘puffery.’” Dismissal reversed.
Note: it seems to me that only one of plaintiff’s §43(a)
theories survives—the theory that BBB falsely advertised quality, not that its
sale of a copycat product constituted false designation of origin, as alleged
in ¶ 62 and repeated as “attempts to claim Hall’s innovations” in ¶ 64. The opinion doesn’t say so outright, but its
discussion is all about quality, and it couldn’t be clearer that Dastar bars the false designation of
origin claim, which is, per the complaint, that by copying the design BBB created
confusion about source. If there’s no
valid trade dress, that’s Dastar-barred. Indeed, the
Federal Circuit was pretty clear about this when discussing 9th
Circuit law a few years back.
The court of appeals also reversed the dismissal of the NY
GBL § 349 and common-law misappropriation claims, for similar reasons. Hall alleged that BBB willfully
misappropriated his product, ideas, and design, and that the deceptive act
under § 349 was the quality/performance claim.
The district court held that Hall didn’t allege injury, even if
customers were misled, but Hall pled that “the extent of the imitation of the
Tote Towel by Defendants” confuses consumers into associating the Tote Towel
with “the inferior Counterfeit Towels,” and that this confusing similarity
harms Hall's reputation. Again, this is
a Dastar-barred theory of injury (or really a Sears/Compco barred theory, though see
below), but the court found that Hall sufficiently pleaded possible injury to
his business.
NY common law bars unjust enrichment. Hall’s claim was based on BBB’s acts “in
accepting Hall's sample towel, ostensibly for consideration of a commercial
relationship, and acting in bad faith by having Hall's towels copied for
commercial benefit.” The complaint alleged misappropriation by “stealing”
Hall’s patented designs. The district court held that Hall failed to plead any
kind of contractual or quasi-contractual relationship, as required. But Hall argued that that line of precedent
applied only to misappropriation of ideas, not misappropriation of labor: he
alleged that “he spent time and money designing the towel, surveying and buying
materials, assessing consumer interest, manufacturing the Tote Towel, and
further efforts, including applying for the '439 Patent.” Thus it was his labor that was
misappropriated, not his idea.
Comment: Hunh? Not only
is this a workaround that can be used to turn any “idea” claim into a “labor”
claim, thus eviscerating the limits on idea misappropriation that have been
carefully developed in order to prevent the cause of action from interfering
with the general freedom to copy, it doesn’t make sense on its own terms: Hall
labored for himself. BBB didn’t somehow
end up with his towels or owning his patent, although it copied his
towels. It’s the results, not the labor,
that BBB allegedly misappropriated; it’s not like Hall painted a BBB store and
didn’t get paid.
The court of appeals still reversed. “New York law does not condone inappropriate
actions, and provides that equitable doctrines may support a misappropriation
claim.” It can impose equitable
obligations to prevent injustice even without an actual agreement between the
parties. Unfair competition can be “any
form of commercial immorality, or simply as endeavoring to reap where one has
not sown.” Thus, the district court
erred in holding a contractual relationship required for misappropriation,
whether the misappropriation is of an idea or of “labor and skill.” Hall provided his sample towel in good faith
and BBB then acted to his detriment, so the claim shouldn’t have been dismissed
on the pleadings.
BBB argued that preemption still barred any NY claim. But
some state regulation of potentially patentable but unpatented subject matter
survives preemption, “in the complex balance between the policy of unencumbered
movement of unpatented ideas, and principles of morality and fairness that are
within state authority.” Hall argued
that BBB didn’t copy a publicly available product, but rather copied a towel he
showed to BBB in the course of discussing a business relationship. Without further elaboration, and with no
explanation of the limits of its ruling, the court held that
principles of patent law preemption
do not override potential causes of action based on unfair commercial
practices. New York misappropriation law extends to “commercial immorality, or
simply as endeavoring to reap where one has not sown.” We conclude that federal
preemption does not apply to the circumstances set forth in the pleadings.
If there was no contractual relationship, or implicit
confidentiality agreement (which is how I'd spin this holding), I have no idea why this would be true. NY misappropriation law may try to extend to reaping where one
hasn’t sown, but that’s why it’s quite
often preempted.
The court upheld the dismissal of BBB’s false advertising
counterclaim, which was brought on the ground that Hall falsely claimed that
his towel was protected by his patent when the patent was really just pending.
The district court found it plain from the pleadings that Hall’s
representations weren’t made with the intent to deceive, and one defendant
appealed on the ground that §43(a) doesn’t require deceptive intent. The court of appeals upheld the dismissal
because no plausible false advertising issue arose under the circumstances of
the case. Likewise, the false marking counterclaim based on Hall’s retention of
the label “patent pending” for a few months after the patent had issued failed
because under the AIA, which applied retrospectively, defendants couldn’t
allege competitive injury.
Judge Lourie dissented from the majority on the design
patent and Lanham Act claims (why not the NY claims?). The district court found the complaint to be
a conflation of facts and theories, making no distinctions (something that
seems to me correct about the quoted §43(a) allegations). The district court asked about the elements
of the towel that merited design patent protection as well as an explanation of
how the BBB towel infringed and how each defendant acted in violation of the
patent laws. True, much of the district
court’s concern related to validity rather than infringement, but “the overall
design of a design patent consists of the particular aspects of the design, and
noting those aspects is not claim construction. How else does one describe a
design except to note the characteristic aspects of the design?” Thus the
dissent found the district court’s actions insufficiently faulty, especially
since the district court invited Hall to replead, and Hall didn’t, which he
should have done. “The judicial system encourages correction of errors when
made, and plaintiff should have paid the penalty for declining that
opportunity.”
As for the Lanham Act, the dissent would have found “performance
that lasts the useful lifetime of the towel” to be “mere puffery, a subjective
claim that cannot be proven true or false and is thus not actionable under the
Lanham Act.” It was an untestable tautology: “the towel lasts as long as it
lasts.” (But could consumers come to a consensus about what it implies? I agree with the majority that it implies more than one
washing—the question is if what it implies is sufficiently measurable to be
falsified. I'd be inclined to think that a very, very flimsy towel could be falsely advertised this way, even though "performance" isn't very specific.)
Friday, January 25, 2013
False claims to have taken class and disliked it not defamatory
Robin Singh Educational Services, Inc. v. Blueprint Test
Preparation, Llc, 2013 WL 240273 (Cal. App. 2 Dist.)
Plaintiff TestMasters sued Blueprint and a number of
principals, who used to be TestMasters employees, for breach of duty and
related shenanigans. Defendants
committed really extensive discovery violations, for which they were
sanctioned, and lost on a number of claims at trial, though the sanction award
substantially exceeded the damages awarded by the jury. I’m only going to
discuss the defamation claims, though the breach of duty etc. claims make juicy
reading.
The jury found that two individual defendants, Triplett and
Riley, along with Blueprint (the business) defamed TestMasters on pre-law/law
school discussion sites. The court found
that there wasn’t substantial evidence to support the jury’s defamation
verdict: although defendants lied about having taken TestMasters’ classes, the
nasty things they said based on those lies weren’t themselves defamatory.
The claim against Triplett was based on a statement that she
posted, pretending to be a student who’d taken a TestMasters class the previous
summer:
Be careful if taking TM. I took it
last summer at UCLA and my instructor was awful, really boring and thick
accent. Actually answered questions
wrong in class and would try to talk his way out of it. Trent was teaching next door and he sounded
awesome, his class looked much better but theywouldn't let me switch, said it
was full. I heard there are a couple
other good instructors but i forgot their names. Probably taking the class over so Im gonna try
to get in trents this time.
Triplett testified that, though she didn’t take the class,
she sat in on a class from an instructor who spoke with such a “very thick
southern accent” that “it was difficult at times to hear what he was
saying.” Triplett stated that Harrison
incorrectly diagrammed a problem on the board, and then “instead of sort of
stepping back he actually tried to explain why that was the correct way to
diagram it.”
Riley made a post in response to a student who had taken a
TestMasters class from Teti (one of the perfidious defendants) and felt that
Teti was “a f-ing jackingass” and “arrogant.”
Riley, pretending also to be a student who took a TestMasters class from
Teti, wrote:
Wow mimi323. I was in a TM UCLA class close to that time
with Trent (I took him for the December test) and all I can say is that there's
no accounting for taste. No offense, and I'm sorry you got that vibe, but I had
a really different experience.
First off, my original teacher
(whose name I wish I knew but blocked out) was terrible- and a lot of people
thought he was just boring and shitty.
… [M]y class sucked so I basically
brided/bullied TM office people to transfer me into his class.
[more praise of Teti]
… And judging from the fact that
his class had more than 100 people in it for the last lesson when my original
class had dwindled to about 10 people by that point, I'm not alone.
Riley testified that he did not have an original TestMasters
class that “sucked” and was “boring and bad,” and that his post actually
referred to an experience that two of his friends at the time (whose last names
he could not remember) told him they had in a TestMasters class at UCLA. Riley
stated that the post was “a true experience of a lot of TestMasters students at
that time period,” but not for him. His
statements about switching classes, and the related claim that he raised his
LSAT score 20 points, were also false.
TestMasters argued that Triplett’s false “first-hand”
account of her instructor’s competence and TestMasters’ unwillingness to let
her switch into Teti’s class were provably false, as were Riley’s statements
that his original class dwindled to about 10 people. This wasn’t support for the jury’s verdict.
Whether a statement contains or implies a provably false
factual claim is a question of law, unless the statement could be interpreted
either innocently or libelously; that exception didn’t apply here. In the context of a discussion board,
statements that TestMasters instructors were “awful,” “really boring,”
“terrible,” “boring,” “shitty,” and “bad,” and they “sucked” couldn’t be
statements of fact or imply provably false assertions of fact. They were classic statements of opinion that
couldn’t be proven true or false. The
accusations of incompetence weren’t made by experts with special skill or
knowledge, whose statements might seem more factual. Since the comments were anonymous, readers
wouldn’t know about Triplett’s experience with LSAT instruction. And anyway, determining whether a teacher is
boring doesn’t usually require expertise.
Some of the statements were or implied provably false assertions
of fact: that a TestMasters instructor answered questions incorrectly in class and tried
to talk his way out of it; that TestMasters refused to allow Triplett to
transfer classes; and that Riley’s class shrunk in size over time from 100 to
10 students because it was so bad that 90 percent of the students left. But TestMasters didn’t introduce evidence
that these statements were false, as it had to do given that LSAT prep is a
matter of public concern. TestMasters
didn’t point to record evidence that the teacher didn’t teach incorrectly, or that it did allow transfers. (This
last bit seems wrong: Triplett said she
wasn’t allowed to transfer, and this was false because she wasn’t in the class. It seems to me that all that’s needed to show
falsity is that she wasn’t in the class and thus couldn’t have been
refused a transfer.) Nor did TestMasters
introduce evidence that its class didn’t dwindle, and Riley testified that he
was taking the experience of “a lot of TestMasters students” as his own. Counsel asked Riley, “So that's false then
where you said that you had a [Testmasters] class that sucked, right?” He said, “right,” but then explained in the
rest of his answer that the statement about the class was true, and the only
part that was not true was that he had taken the class.
The court noted that “the statements by Triplett and Riley
that they were TestMasters students were very provably and indeed admittedly
false assertions of fact, but they are not defamatory.” Thus, the awards on the defamation claims
were struck. (At the very least, a false advertising claim would proceed differently
in that the defendants clearly made false establishment claims—their substantiation,
that they had actually taken the classes, was admittedly false.)
preliminary injunction mandates corrective advertising for literal falsity
Generac Power Systems, Inc. v. Kohler Co., 2013 WL 238843
(E.D. Wis.)
Previously, the
court denied Generac’s motion for a Lanham Act preliminary injunction on the
ground that materials sent to over 1200 dealers weren’t commercial advertising
or promotion. After the Seventh
Circuit’s decision in Neuros
Co., Ltd. v. KTurbo, Inc., 698 F.3d 514 (7th Cir. 2012), the court granted
Generac’s motion for reconsideration on that point.
Generac had already established that Kohler's statement that
the Generac Generator lacks a “Low–Speed Diagnostic Exercise” was literally
false. Falsity was enough to lead to a finding of irreparable injury in the
context of comparative advertising (citing McCarthy and Axiom).
Kohler argued that injunctive relief was moot because the
offending handbook was no longer in circulation. Still, Generac argued that, to avoid the
lingering impact of the false advertising, Kohler should be required to inform
dealers and distributors of the falsity of its statements and to instruct them
to destroy the old handbook. The question was whether the harm Generac would
suffer in the absence of an injunction was greater than the harm that Kohler
would suffer if it were granted. The
more likely a plaintiff is to prevail, the less heavily need the balance of
harms favor it. Kohler argued that,
given the narrow audience of dealers and the lack of evidence about how they
used the handbook, the remote possibility of lost goodwill was less weighty
than the harm to Kohler of having to take unnecessary corrective action and
harming its own reputation.
The court disagreed, given Generac’s strong probability of
prevailing on the merits. The harm to
Generac was the risk of continued dissemination of the falsity in existing
copies of the handbook. Since Kohler
didn’t tell its dealers why it provided a replacement handbook or direct them
to destroy the prior version, the remaining steps were necessary to eradicate
any residual effects of the false advertising.
Kohler also argued that the public interest was minimal
because the parties provided consumers with lots of advertising related to
their respective generators. But it’s
always in the public’s interest to have truth replace falsity. Thus, Kohler would be required to inform its
dealers and distributors of the falsity of its statement and instruct them to
destroy any remaining copies or CDs of the Handbook.
Generac asked for attorneys’ fees because Kohler dragged the
case out for eleven months after ceasing distribution of its false statements,
but the court didn’t find that the case was exceptional.
Wednesday, January 23, 2013
Lawyers in remix culture
In the grand tradition of Larry Lessig RPF (real person fiction), we now have Mark Andrews, a video celebrating the rapper's lawyer's successful defense of his name. HT Mark Edward Andrews.
Is patent infringement theft?
E.I. Du Pont de Nemours and Co. v. Heraeus Precious Metals
North America Conshohocken LLC, 2013 WL 214292 (D. Or.)
DuPont sued Heraeus for patent infringement. Heraeus counterclaimed for, among other
things, false advertising, based on a DuPont press release, “DuPont Addresses
Patent Protection at Solarbuzz China Conference; Intellectual Property Theft
Growing in Competitive Climate of Photovoltaics.” The press release stated that a DuPont managing
director, as a featured speaker at a conference, said that “Intellectual
Property (IP) theft is widespread and the issue seems to be growing in the current
climate of this industry…. We do not ignore infringement and will pursue
aggressively other points in the PV supply chain where IP infringement of our
PV metallization pastes exists.” The
press release continued:
Cheng indicated this set of actions
continues in the manner of previous DuPont actions involving IP protection in
China and other countries in the world. The company recently filed two lawsuits
against PV metallization paste supplier Heraeus and one against its customer
SolarWorld, for infringing on DuPont patents for DuPontTM Solamet® PV
metallization pastes.
Cheng asked for increased support
from the industry to guard against infringement and stronger opposition to the
use of “infringing” materials in the production and sale of downstream products
by cell and module makers, PV system developers, installers and owners.
Infringing companies expose themselves, and potentially others they do business
with, to the full range of legal remedies.
Heraeus argued that DuPont’s statement that Heraeus engaged
in IP theft was false and misleading.
Though this statement didn’t appear in precisely those words in the
press release, it was a reasonable inference that could be drawn from the press
release, given the juxtaposition of statements about IP theft and statements about
DuPont's lawsuits against Heraeus. “[I]n
stating it has filed two lawsuits against Heraeus alleging patent infringement
(a statement that is true on its face), DuPont is, ipso facto, alleging Heraeus
has committed intellectual property theft.”
While Heraeus argued that DuPont’s statement was false because DuPont’s
lawsuits failed to allege any copying, misappropriation, willfulness or other
conduct that could be reasonably characterized as “theft,” the court thought
that was a mistake. Because a patent is
IP, the distinction between “patent infringement” and “IP theft” is a
distinction without a difference.
(Really? Could Heraeus be
prosecuted for selling stolen property, then?
For purposes of a Lanham Act false advertising counterclaim, I agree
with the court, but that hardly means there’s no difference between theft and
infringement.)
Because the counterclaim depended on a patentee’s assertion
of its patent rights, in addition to the ordinary Lanham Act elements, Heraeus
was also required to allege bad faith, which it didn’t do. The counterclaim was dismissed with leave to
amend.
Tuesday, January 22, 2013
Reading list: comic law
James Daily & Ryan Davidson, The Law of Superheroes: Based on lawandthemultiverse.com, this breezy book has the benefit of plenty of illustrations, but its presentation of the law is generally devoid of nuance. While it’s not wrong for the sake of drama the way a Law & Order episode or a comic book might be, it’s probably a much better read for nonlawyers. It starts with two statements of note from an IP perspective, for two different reasons. First, there’s
The authors immediately follow with the preposterous statement that “[t]he terms ‘superhero’ and ‘supervillain’ are trademarks co-owned by Marvel Characters, Inc. and DC Comics, Inc. These terms are used throughout this book solely to refer descriptively to Marvel and DC characters.” I don’t presume to know whether Marvel & DC asked for this ridiculous disclaimer in return for agreeing not to contest the extensive and helpful (and fair use!) images in the book, but, just to be clear: (1) superhero and supervillain are generic terms, not trademarks (ETA: yes, I know there's a registration; that just makes Marvel & DC aggressive and well-funded, not trademark owners); (2) even if they weren’t generic, the owner (since a trademark must have an owner, not two who don’t control each other’s behavior) would not have any claim against a book that used a term “wrongly.”
But at least this is a good indication of what you’re going to get: some entertaining/shallow discussion of various legal dilemmas in which comics characters might find themselves. I did like the discussion of masked superheroes testifying in court, and the point that DC has solved this problem with a constitutional amendment allowing “registered meta-humans” to testify masked, which then means that DC has already put in place the very provision that in the Marvelverse sparked Civil War: “while the DC workaround would be effective in the courts, it does not seem as if that universe has fully dealt with the implications of that solution.” Heh.
Unfortunately, while sensitive to the First Amendment implications of anti-mask laws, the authors badly mishandle the idea of newsworthiness when it comes to invasion of privacy, claiming that Peter Parker would have a cause of action against someone who revealed that he was Spiderman because Peter Parker “is just a working stiff, a news photographer and, perhaps most importantly, is often written as a minor. The public probably doesn’t have as much of an interest in knowing these details.” Um, no. Dude is Spiderman. That his secret identity seems like an ordinary Joe is no more relevant to whether the Spiderman-Peter Parker link is newsworthy than the ordinariness of the contents of Anthony Weiner’s boxer-briefs is relevant to the newsworthiness of the fact that a Congressman was sending pictures of his erection around. So, as the authors suggest, don’t take the book as offering legal advice--but it's an interesting entry into the category "what people think the law is."
So why comic books? Well, for one thing, they’re both interesting and popular. The main problem with a lot of legal educational materials is that they are boring…. So rather than making up people who may not even have names, or using cases involving people you’ve never heard of, The Law of Superheroes uses characters you already know and love.To a copyright lawyer, that sounds intriguingly like a description of using another’s work simply to avoid the drudgery of working up something fresh, or simply to get attention—something that would in theory count against the book in a fair use analysis, even though the book is obviously fair use. You can use someone else’s work to get attention under many circumstances, including when you want to teach them law.
The authors immediately follow with the preposterous statement that “[t]he terms ‘superhero’ and ‘supervillain’ are trademarks co-owned by Marvel Characters, Inc. and DC Comics, Inc. These terms are used throughout this book solely to refer descriptively to Marvel and DC characters.” I don’t presume to know whether Marvel & DC asked for this ridiculous disclaimer in return for agreeing not to contest the extensive and helpful (and fair use!) images in the book, but, just to be clear: (1) superhero and supervillain are generic terms, not trademarks (ETA: yes, I know there's a registration; that just makes Marvel & DC aggressive and well-funded, not trademark owners); (2) even if they weren’t generic, the owner (since a trademark must have an owner, not two who don’t control each other’s behavior) would not have any claim against a book that used a term “wrongly.”
But at least this is a good indication of what you’re going to get: some entertaining/shallow discussion of various legal dilemmas in which comics characters might find themselves. I did like the discussion of masked superheroes testifying in court, and the point that DC has solved this problem with a constitutional amendment allowing “registered meta-humans” to testify masked, which then means that DC has already put in place the very provision that in the Marvelverse sparked Civil War: “while the DC workaround would be effective in the courts, it does not seem as if that universe has fully dealt with the implications of that solution.” Heh.
Unfortunately, while sensitive to the First Amendment implications of anti-mask laws, the authors badly mishandle the idea of newsworthiness when it comes to invasion of privacy, claiming that Peter Parker would have a cause of action against someone who revealed that he was Spiderman because Peter Parker “is just a working stiff, a news photographer and, perhaps most importantly, is often written as a minor. The public probably doesn’t have as much of an interest in knowing these details.” Um, no. Dude is Spiderman. That his secret identity seems like an ordinary Joe is no more relevant to whether the Spiderman-Peter Parker link is newsworthy than the ordinariness of the contents of Anthony Weiner’s boxer-briefs is relevant to the newsworthiness of the fact that a Congressman was sending pictures of his erection around. So, as the authors suggest, don’t take the book as offering legal advice--but it's an interesting entry into the category "what people think the law is."
Sunday, January 20, 2013
Patent law, after xkcd
Patent law explained (perhaps) using the most common ten hundred words. After xkcd's Upgoer 5, and facilitated by the subsequently created Upgoer 5 Text Editor. Your call on how ironic that is.
Saturday, January 19, 2013
Subway has a nice knock-down argument against length complaints
Subway says "footlong" is just a descriptive (um, wouldn't that be deceptively misdescriptive?) trademark, not a statement about length.
'When I use a word,' Humpty Dumpty said, in rather a scornful tone, 'it means just what I choose it to mean — neither more nor less.'Lewis Carroll, Through the Looking Glass, Ch. 6
'The question is,' said Alice, 'whether you can make words mean so many different things.'
'The question is,' said Humpty Dumpty, 'which is to be master — that's all.'
Friday, January 18, 2013
Knockoff Economy, Session IV
David Opderbeck (Seton Hall University School of Law; Notre
Dame Law School)
Photos: Flickr, iStockphoto: a CC regime establishes both an
open- and closed-source community. Can
pay $5 for a very professional-looking image.
You need copyright to support the dual model.
Pushing back on specific examples. Fashion: what really matters in fashion is
the TM/brand. Consulting on Coach fabric—company
bought 20 rolls of vinyl fabric with the Coach brand on it; selling swathes to
people on Etsy who presumably were making iPhone cases. Coach sued, listing 100
TMs, including 2 on fabric, but Coach doesn’t sell fabric at retail; instead
they supply it to contractors. Asking
for millions in statutory damages for the logo.
Cuisine: parts of a dish are known while parts are
innovative—but is this a completely unique community because it’s so different
from other creatives?
Comedy: can we really say that norm enforcement that
includes occasional beatdowns is a superior form of regulation? Connection/history with organized crime. What supports a willingness to use violence?
Football: League is a cartel; league is very strict about
TMs and other IP; highly specified what the team can do, what only the league
can do, what the players can do. There, underlying copying norm is the notion
that the cartel would fall apart if someone could monopolize a play that would
always win. Probably true for the NCAA.
What about high school? The
league may have norms of a certain kind of competition. Not competitors slugging it out in an open
market, but a closed cartel.
Fonts: thinks that fonts are overproduced; 5000 fonts you
get with your purchase are marketing, not used.
Finance: are trade secrets as important as the authors
say? Tacit knowledge is important, as it
is in biotech. People jealously protect
tacit knowledge developed in the lab.
Knowing what a client prefers isn’t really a trade secret, but not
something you want to share either.
Lea Shaver (Indiana University Robert H. McKinney School of
Law)
Consider willingness to share smaller share of larger
pie. One theory: provide maximum rewards
to the person most responsible for the pie.
Anyone else who takes a piece is stealing. But that wrongly assumes a pie of fixed size.
Case study of early light bulb industry—Edison’s patent
litigation strategy. Early industry:
people knock off designs because they don’t understand the patents and are too
poorly financed to sue anyway. Innovation
is everywhere. Edison, who’s financed
and has an emperor’s view of his Lockean role, chases everyone else out. Innovation slows; maybe a Pyrrhic victory.
Don’t fall into the fallacy of the fixed pie. IP enforcement
can be less rational viewed over a longer timeframe; hard to convince firms
with a shortterm mentality to see benefits of competition.
Implicit in the book is a question of distributive justice
and innovation. Knockoff seems to make innovation affordable to the masses—trickle-down
theory.
South Africa: English books are readily available, as are
books in Afrikaans (for white minority w/sufficient disposable income to induce
robust regime), but you don’t see many works in Zulu or !Xhosa, not because
people can’t read in those language—a Zulu newspaper publishing industry has
arisen. May come down to the fact that
the community isn’t wealthy enough to afford the copyright model of innovation. Transaction costs/can’t deliver innovation
cheaply. We should modify copyright to
allow translations, which could allow the industry to thrive and then Zulu authors
could also earn a living by accepting a smaller share of a larger pie.
Fred von Lohmann (Google)
Kept thinking of the dysfunction of policymaking. Why can’t legislators deal with the richness
and variety of these fields? Rep. Kastenmeier
& Michael Renner, who served on his staff for many years: Kastenmeier used
to view requests for extensions/expansions of exclusive rights in relation to a
principle from David Lange (influenced by a law professor!): a civil procedure
for copyright reform proposals. Four
burdens of proof for new copyright legislation to expand exclusive rights—proponent
ought to show that the interest can fit harmoniously within the existing legal
framework; proponent must be able to commit the new expression to a reasonably
clear and satisfactory definition—the sort of thing you could explain to the
average member of Congress (many provisions of current law flunck this); honest
analysis of costs and benefits of proposed legislation—the argument that a
particular interest group will make more money and thus be more creative doesn’t
satisfy this standard or the requirements of the Copyright Clause; and finally,
any advocate of a new interest should show how giving protection will enrich or
enhance the aggregate public domain—the public gain should outweigh the private
benefit. It’s this last part that’s the most important.
If you ask not “would comedians/fashion industry be better
off?” but “would the public benefit exceed the benefit to the comedians/fashion
industry?” the answers would be very clear.
But he’s never heard anyone explain how the public would benefit more than
the recording artists from enhancements to recording artists’ rights.
Peter DiCola’s results from survey of
5000 working musicians. Revenue
sources were 80%, on average, not related to copyright or at best indirectly
related to copyright. Echoed The KE’s
themes. Robust incentives that are remote from what we think of as the
copyright incentive/monopoly model.
Dave Fagundes (Southwestern Law School; University of Miami
School of Law)
Last-mover advantage.
Derby, like football, is an open-source strategic innovation world. May be dying for lots of reasons, including
bad business model; it’s kind of a novelty and most people don’t come
back. New strategic innovation: slow
derby, both highly effective and horrible to watch. You can typically gain points more
effectively with this strategy; but whether it’s worse is contested—participants
say it’s more interesting for players and rewards different kinds of play and
strategies. Ass’n is trying to intervene
to change the rules against this, but hasn’t been able to do so.
The KE is useful
for taking things that are in plain sight and pointing out that they have
implications that are not in plain sight.
Puzzle, though: there are a lot of angry people in this book. Louis CK is made at Dane Cook, etc. Third parties are also mad at copiers. Why
are they mad if they’re not losing money or prestige? Third parties have no monetary investment in
brand even if we believe dilution theories.
They should be happy about the positive effects of copying on a brand!
They’re mad because they feel like they got ripped off,
which triggers an instinctive sense of moral outrage. Highlights a difference between the way The KE thinks about unauthorized use and
how it’s actually experienced. In this
room, we think of unauthorized copying as an economic phenomenon that can be
optimized. Owners, authors, some third parties at least sometimes see it as a
deeply harmful activity that inflicts expressive harm. Many people say it wasn’t about economic harm
or brand dilution: someone stole my name!
Speaking a different moral language.
Moral psychology language, primary popular expositor
Jonathan Haidt. Basic claim: moral
reasoning is something like innate—organized in advance of experience. Just as we use heuristics to perceive the
world, we have the equivalent of moral heuristics. Basic descriptive claim: these moral
heuristics are not just the harm
principle, but feature different dyads: justice/fairness, sanctity/perversion,
loyalty/betrayal. They vary a lot among
cultures and people. Some people are fine with copying.
What is to be done?
Counterpoint to claim made in The
KE, which is about social benefits of unauthorized copying. Can represent an additional social cost
beyond the ones we usually think about.
Demoralization costs of observing work being copied, for the copied
person or for third parties. Maybe
dynamic costs for people who experience sense of moral loss; maybe they’ll be
less trusting in creative process.
Why aren’t people more receptive to this? Gets to what law
can do about copying and what industry can do.
Resistance to copying among substantial percentage of population is
going to exert gravitational pull—hard for law to encourage more copying. Sees this as a teacher. American copyright law has tons of natural
rights language. If people are not
consciously adopting the content of law, they will have a hard time changing
reactions no matter what law says.
Moral psychology helps us understand why self-governance
pops up. Norms coalesce around behavior.
Not just a norm story in the sense of coming from other people; feels
like it’s coming from the self.
Sprigman: we criminalized adultery for a long time; the
moral intuitions are deep but that doesn’t mean that we want the law to
intervene. Also endogenous—if you change
the rules, people understand that the rules allow copying, and people like what
they’re used to.
Von Lohmann: some idea that the tweaker is lining its
pockets at the expense of the originator—but if there’s competition, the
tweaker doesn’t keep social surplus—in the competitive market of VCR makers,
the price falls to marginal cost; the benefit goes to consumer surplus. Maybe that’s wasting some valuable asset, but
the idea that the follow-on innovator is rentseeking doesn’t work if the market
in that segment is competitive.
Opderbeck: Games sometimes prevent even the innovator from
using the innovation—that’s one thing a cartel can do if it slows down the
game.
Von Lohmann: Mixed martial arts also had “bad” innovation—resulted
in combatants immediately going to ground in very static wrestling holds: made
matches unfun to watch and very short.
McKenna: across sports—NFL rule changes are intended to
score more.
Buccafusco: not “bad” just subject to different incentives.
McKenna: likely to cost the group a bunch of money (in the
long term—arguably this happened to the brand of college debate in which
Fagundes & I engaged).
Buccafusco: moral intuitions are sufficient to allow people
to find harm when they’re told they need to in order to impose a sanction. (Not automatically, but definitely there are
big swings in the research I saw.) But
they can be debiased.
Raustiala: we focused on the central question of what causes
innovation, and not so much about who gets the gains, but that’s a huge
issue. Often happens that larger pies
lead to greater distribution of benefits, he believes. Shepherd Fairey: really pissed off that his
fashion line is often knocked off.
Illustrates that people have moral intuitions, but they find ways to
make those fit their economic interests.
McKenna: it’s not just economic interests; it’s that you don’t
have a fully explicated sense of which copying is wrong. CVS always locates next to Walgreen’s and
vice versa, and no one sees that as wrong just because the other ID’d a market.
Heller: in European laws that could be unfair competition.
Von Lohmann: doubts anyone in the book would have an
objection to a purely personal copier—a restaurant will happily share a recipe
with an ordinary citizen.
Sprigman: one comedian said, “If you can use one of my jokes
to improve your lame life, go ahead.” Fashion designers say that their rights
shouldn’t apply to home sewing.
Ellickson: maybe it’s a Lockean norm, I made it so I should
own it—but that’s not what you really see in the world. To allow property in football plays would be
destructive of the league, so efficiency demands no rights; but is there any
moral outrage that is just trumped by other considerations?
Sprigman: the moral outrage tends to be directed at the
innovation.
Me: I think Fagundes makes a great point; the question is
how that psychology gets operationalized in any given society—because it’s
clearly very different across times and places, as well as with ingroups and outgroups. E.g., Joe Karaganis’s copying study shows
that many people don’t take very much account of the interests of distant
record companies. Likewise you see different
cultural results in the dictator
game, on a base that is stable (people like fairness).
Fagundes: doesn’t think moral outrage is itself a reason to
grant rights, but something to be factored into calculate. Is Hume right? Do we begin with intuitions and then reason
our way to them? No one knows whether copyright
really promotes progress of science/useful arts; maybe we should stop
pretending we know the answer. The Qs
are empirical in that people differ even individually as well as within
culture. If something is seen as a
transgression, then it triggers your sense of wrongness; if you don’t have that
heuristic and just think in terms of economic harm, you’ll never see that as a
problem. Compare consensus about what’s
transgression in football (copying plays is ok) versus no consensus in fashion
(big disagreements about what copying is ok).
Von Lohmann: moral intuitions have a distributional element.
Vast difference in revenue distributions depending on how successful musicians
are—if you’re making over $200,000/year off of music, sources of your revenue
more likely to be copyright-related.
Young musicians starting out may have a very different moral compass
compared to older/successful ones, influenced in both cases by economic
situations.
Shaver: not Lockean; she thinks people often think ideas
should be protected, and they don’t give moral credit to the people who take
the idea and make it operational/executable; they think of the patent system as
kind of a lottery.
Fagundes: people angry on behalf of third parties make the
pure Lockean story harder to tell.
(Though wanting to enforce norms can come from a Lockean place, I’d
think.)
McKenna: the NFL might well step in to stop teams from
protecting plays, but that doesn’t explain why the copying norm exists in the first
place. At the very bottom level, the reason why there’s no norm against copying
in football is that it would be unmasculine. You win by dominating, not by
whining about the play used. Also,
coaches make a reputation by being able to come up with a new thing and staying
ahead on a week to week basis.
However, some ways of copying would be deeply offensive.
Teams share game tape, now enforced through conferences but by norm first. You’d be shamed for not complying. But if someone spied on practices, or on a
playbook, that would be deeply offensive.
You have to figure it out on your own, and only once we put it out on
the field. Has to do with first mover
advantages. Can’t take away our chance
to have a successful play.
Also, people get mad when there’s too much innovation. Cultural norm about who gets to define what
the game is—you’re playing some other game if you change it too much. (Along with policy debate, see: golf and the ADA;
letter
values in Scrabble.)
Raustiala: interests of designer/chef in being
innovator/being copied can be very different from that of a firm by which s/he’s
employed. Better reputation as innovator
allows you to move up—a principal/agent problem that needs to be considered.
One thing that ties our examples together is that they’re often individuals.
McKenna: firms who are most interested in sharing are also
the most innovative—feel they can stay ahead and improve their reputations.
Von Lohmann: engineers in Silicon Valley can also get a lot
of reputational capital from sharing code.
Ellickson: doesn’t share the intuition that firms are
constrained more by norms than individuals—individual deviance is more highly
distributed. (Depends on which kinds of
norms, it seems to me—Fox News was mentioned.
Herein we are talking about norms about freedom to copy and the extra
benefits available to individuals when there’s free copying and improved
reputation that don’t accrue to their firms, not norms about how accounting
will be done or whether your clients are muppets.)
Sprigman: Institutional conservatism can keep a
client/institution out of trouble. Not
so much about law but about norms of enforcement agencies. In the financial crisis, stuff got done that
wouldn’t have gotten done in earlier regimes, with really aggressive advice
from lawyers. Firms read the law and asked what they could do, not what the
norms were.